• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

Social-ecological systems and institutions

2. L ITERATURE R EVIEW (P1): W HAT CAN ECONOMIC EXPERIMENTS TELL US

2.2. Social-ecological systems and institutions

In the most general way, a social-ecological system (SES) comprises a social system, an ecological system, and the interactions between the two. Traditionally, ecosystem analysis has studied the impact of human and geophysical drivers of ecosystem change in isolation.

The definition of a SES goes beyond this view. SESs are defined as coherent systems with multiple (often non-linear) interactions that span across (hierarchically linked) scales, which consist of critical resources, whose flows and uses are affected by both social and ecological factors, and which are dynamic and adaptive (Redman et al., 2004).

According to Ostrom (2009), a SES can also be viewed as comprising four “first-level core subsystems,” namely: (1) a resource system, (2) resource units, (3) a governance system, and (4) users. A set of “second-level” variables that are useful for SES analysis, and which can be sorted by these core sub-systems, has also been identified. Institutions are part of both social sub-systems, i.e. the governance systems and users. More specifically, the overall property-rights system, operational, collective-choice, and constitutional rules are variables of the governance system, while norms are a variable of the user system (Ostrom, 2009). Focusing on this point, and in the spirit of structuration theory (Giddens, 1984), the following sections will focus on understanding the structure–agency dynamics of institutions and institutional change.

2.2.1. Institutions between structure, agency, and evolution

There is still relatively little agreement on the basic concepts in institutional economics, or in the words of Arild Vatn (2005): “Just as there are many theories of what institutions are and what they do, there are certainly also many different ways of explaining their development and change.” It is not the aim of this paper to present an exhaustive review of this ongoing debate; others have already done this (Hodgson, 2006; Hodgson, 1998;

Schmid, 2004; Vatn, 2005; Zikos and Thiel, 2013). Rather, I would like to show that it is useful to distinguish between (1) structural, (2) agent-based, and (3) evolutionary approaches of institutions (Hodgson, 2004), with the aim to better understand the concept of institution on which particular, empirically grounded economic experiments are based.

Vatn (2005) distinguishes two ways of defining an institution. Institutions can either be viewed as “external reward structures” that constrain (North, 1990) or enable (Bromley, 1989) agents, or as “internalized motivations” of economic agents (Berger and Luckmann, 1967). The structural view is most prominently represented by Douglass North, who defines institutions as “humanly devised constraints that structure political, economic and social interaction” (North, 1991). To the contrary, Berger and Luckmann (1967) view institutions as embedded in economic agents, representing a “reciprocal typification of habitualized actions by types of actors.” The two viewpoints are sometimes combined, resulting in an understanding of institutions as consisting “of cognitive, normative, and regulative structures and activities” (Scott, 1995).

Evolutionary economic theory emphasizes that institutions are endogenous to the economic process (Herrmann-Pillath, 2013; Hodgson, 1998; van Bergh and Stagl, 2003) and

ontologically not reducible to their structural or agent-based aspects (Hodgson, 2004).

Both economic agents – with their shared beliefs and (limited) cognition – and structures play a role in the establishment and change of institutions. It has been pointed out that especially the cognitive aspects have been much neglected in (institutional) economics. A psychological or even neurological perspective on context-dependence, framing of decisions, habitualization, and their temporal dynamics could shed new light on the processes that constitute institutional choice (Herrmann-Pillath, 2013; Hodgson, 2004;

Schlüter, 2009). Put differently, preferences for institutions are endogenous, dynamically changing over time, and domain-specific (Herrmann-Pillath, 2013).

2.2.2. Institutional change

By definition, “[i]nstitutional change covers both the process of changing an existing institution and the establishment of an institution in a field where no institution has existed before” (Vatn, 2005). In an overview on theories of institutional change, Vatn (2005) draws a distinction between spontaneous and designed institutional change. This change can come from “below,” as the result of deliberative action, or it may result from “pure”

spontaneous change. Theories of “designed institutional change” can be categorized into those “driven by efficiency considerations” and those “driven by the intent to protect specific interests or values” (Vatn, 2005).

More generally, objective institutional design is viewed as exogenous to the affected agents; it is principally limited to an alteration of the incentive structure; and it assumes stable preferences (Alexander, 2005; Goodin, 1996; Thiel et al., 2014). This perspective is equivalent to what I will call the structural perspective on institutional change throughout this paper. In contrast, subjective institutional design is assumed to affect actors’ beliefs and cognition (Aoki, 2011) and will in the following also be called the agent-based view on institutional change. In a third, evolutionary viewpoint, these two are combined in a process, with feedback loops existing between agents and structures. Further, it is assumed that agents can impact institutions through choice. Institutions governing social-ecological systems will also relate to properties of the two systems; they may be affected by the framing of the discourse, or the underlying epistemology. Under these conditions, institutions may also evolve as outcomes of social learning processes (Ison et al., 2014;

Ison et al., 2007).

A major achievement was made by Hodgson (2004) in singling out the structure and agency aspects of institutions in the evolutionary framework: institutions as structures1 affect the distribution of resources, agents’ preferences, and subsequent institutional choice of agents (cf. Hodgson, 2004; van Bergh and Stagl, 2003). In this process, institutions and preferences co-evolve. It may thus be difficult to find an (objective) starting point for analyzing institutional change. This chicken and egg problem was also stressed by Field (1984), who shows the limits of game theoretical reasoning and the efficiency view on institutions in neoclassical microeconomics (cf. Vatn, 2005). Likewise, Hodgson (2004) emphasizes that in the study of institutional change it:

“is simply arbitrary to stop at one particular stage in the explanation and say ‘it is all reducible to individuals’ just as much as to say it is ‘all social and institutional’. The key point is that in this infinite regress, neither individual nor institutional factors have legitimate explanatory primacy. The idea that all explanations have ultimately be in terms of individuals (or institutions) is thus unfounded. Once we admit that the individual is socially determined then we have an explanatory infinite regress, and neither individuals nor institutions can be the legitimate final term.”

Summing up, institutions can be viewed as structures exogenous to the agent, or as cognitive media embedded solely in the agent. In contrast, evolutionary institutional economics highlights the inseparable co-evolution of institutional structures and agents’

cognition, beliefs, behavior, and choice. In the following, I will show that the three viewpoints of institutions outlined here are implicitly reflected in the practice of experimental economists.