• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

Scoringrulesforjudgmentaggregation Dietrich,Franz MunichPersonalRePEcArchive

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Aktie "Scoringrulesforjudgmentaggregation Dietrich,Franz MunichPersonalRePEcArchive"

Copied!
32
0
0

Wird geladen.... (Jetzt Volltext ansehen)

Volltext

(1)

Munich Personal RePEc Archive

Scoring rules for judgment aggregation

Dietrich, Franz

CNRS (Paris, France), UEA (Norwich, U.K.)

26 December 2011

Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/36892/

MPRA Paper No. 36892, posted 24 Feb 2012 14:31 UTC

(2)

Scoring rules for judgment aggregation

Franz Dietrich1

December 2011 (minor revisions later)

Abstract

This paper studies a class of judgment aggregation rules, to be called ‘scoring rules’ after their famous counterpart in preference aggregation theory. A scoring rule delivers the collective judgments which reach the highest total ‘score’ across the individuals, subject to the judgments having to be rational. Depending on how we define ‘scores’, we obtain several (old and new) solutions to the judgment aggregation problem, such as distance- based aggregation, premise- and conclusion-based aggregation, truth-tracking rules, and a Borda-type rule. Scoring rules are shown to generalize the classical scoring rules of preference aggregation theory.

JEL Classification: D70, D71

Keywords: judgment aggregation, social choice, scoring rules, Hamming rule, Borda rule, premise- and conclusion-based rules

1 Introduction

The judgment aggregation problem consists in merging many individuals’ yes/no judgments on some interconnected propositions into collective yes/no judgments on these propositions.

The classical example, born in legal theory, is that three jurors in a court trial disagree on which of the following three propositions are true: the defendant has broken the contract (p); the contract is legally valid (q); the defendant is liable (r). According to a univer- sally accepted legal doctrine, r (the ‘conclusion’) is true if and only if p and r (the two

‘premises’) are both true. So, r is logically equivalent to p∧q. The simplest rule to ag- gregate the jurors’ judgments — namely propositionwise majority voting — may generate logically inconsistent collective judgments, as Table 1 illustrates. There are of course nu-

premisep premiseq conclusionr(⇔p∧q)

Individual 1 Yes Yes Yes

Individual 2 Yes No No

Individual 3 No Yes No

Majority Yes Yes No

Table 1: The classical example of logically inconsistent majority judgments merous other possible ‘agendas’, i.e., kinds of interconnected propositions a group might face. Preference aggregation is a special case with propositions of the form ‘xis better than

1CNRS, Cerses, Paris, France & UEA, Norwich, U.K. Mail: post@franzdietrich.net. Web:

www.franzdietrich.net.

(3)

y’ (for many alternatives x and y), where these propositions are interconnected through standard conditions such as transitivity. In this context, Condorcet’s classicalvoting para- dox about cyclical majority preferences is nothing but another example of inconsistent majority judgments. Starting with List and Pettit’s (2002) seminal paper, a whole series of contributions have explored which judgment aggregation rules can be used, depending on, firstly, the agenda in question, and, secondly, the requirements placed on aggregation, such as anonymity, and of course the consistency of collective judgments. Some theorems generalize Arrow’s Theorem from preference to judgment aggregation (Dietrich and List 2007, Dokow and Holzman 2010; both build on Nehring and Puppe 2010a and strengthen Wilson 1975). Other theorems have no immediate counterparts in classical social choice theory (e.g., List 2004, Dietrich 2006a, 2010, Nehring and Puppe 2010b, Dietrich and Mongin 2010).

It is fair to say that judgment aggregation theory has until recently been dominated by ‘impossibility’ findings, as is evident from theSymposium on Judgment Aggregation in Journal of Economic Theory (C. List and B. Polak eds., 2010, vol. 145(2)). The recent conference ‘Judgment aggregation and voting’ (Freudenstadt, 2011) however marks a visible shift of attention towards constructing concrete aggregation rules and finding ‘second best’

solutions in the face of impossibility results. The new proposals range from a first Borda- type aggregation rule (Zwicker 2011) to, among others, new distance-based rules (Duddy and Piggins 2011) and rules which approximate the majority judgments when these are inconsistent (Nehring, Pivato and Puppe 2011). The more traditional proposals include premise- and conclusion-based rules (e.g., Kornhauser and Sager 1986, Pettit 2001, List &

Pettit 2002, Dietrich 2006, Dietrich and Mongin 2010), sequential rules (e.g., List 2004, Dietrich and List 2007b), distance-based rules (e.g., Konieszni and Pino-Perez 2002, Pigozzi 2006, Miller and Osherson 2008, Eckert and Klamler 2009), and quota rules with well- calibrated acceptance thresholds and varous degrees of collective rationality (e.g., Dietrich and List 2007b; see also Nehring and Puppe 2010a).

The present paper contributes to the theory’s current ‘constructive’ effort by investi- gating a class of aggregation rules to be calledscoring rules. The inspiration comes from classical scoring rules in preference aggregation theory. These rules generate collective pref- erences which rank each alternative according to the sum-total ‘score’ it receives from the group members, where the ‘score’ could be defined in different ways, leading to different classical scoring rules such as Borda rule (see Smith 1973, Young 1975, and for abstract generalizations Myerson 1995, Zwicker 2008 and Pivato 2011b). In a general judgment aggregation framework, however, there are no ‘alternatives’; so our scoring rules are based on assigning scores to propositions, not alternatives. Nonetheless, our scoring rules are related to classical scoring rules, and generalize them, as will be shown.

The paradigm underlying our scoring rules — i.e., the maximization of total score of collective judgments — differs from standard paradigms in judgment aggregation, such as the premise-, conclusion- or distance-based paradigms. Nonetheless, it will turn out that several existing rules can be re-modelled as scoring rules, and can thus be ‘rationalized’ in terms of the maximization of total scores. Of course, the way scores are being assigned to propositions — the ‘scoring’ — differs strongly across rules; for instance, the Hamming rule and the premise-based rule can each be viewed as a scoring rule, but with respect to two very different scorings. This paper explores various plausible scorings. It uncovers the scorings which implicitly underlie several well-known aggregation rules, and suggests other scorings which generate novel aggregation rules. For instance, a particularly natural

(4)

scoring, to be called reversal scoring, will lead to a new generalization of Borda rule from preference aggregation to judgment aggregation. The problem of how to generalize Borda rule has been a long-lasting open question in judgment aggregation theory. Recently, an interesting, though so far incomplete, proposal was made by Zwicker (2011) (who told me that also Conal Duddy and Ashley Piggins have independent work in progress about this).

Surprisingly, Zwicker’s and the present Borda generalizations are distinctively different.

Though large, the class of scoring rules is far from universal: some important aggrega- tion rules fall outside this class (notably the mentioned rule approximating the majority judgments, by Nehring, Pivato and Puppe 2011). I will also investigate a natural general- ization of scoring rules, to be calledset scoring rules, which are based on assigning scores to entire judgment sets rather than single propositions (judgments). Set scoring rules are for instance interesting in the context of epistemic (‘truth-tracking’) aggregation models, where they have recently been studied by Pivato (2011a).

I could have written this paper by focusing exclusively on one specific application of scoring rules (for instance, the problem of extending Borda rule). However, I chose to give the paper a broader scope, not only to do justice to the diverse applications of scoring rules, but also to be useful at the theory’s current stage of searching for concrete mechanisms. I hope that the ideas and perspectives offered below will be stimulating and inspiring.

After this introduction, Section 2 defines the general framework, Section 3 analyses various scoring rules, Section 4 goes on to analyse several set scoring rules, and Section 5 draws some conclusions about where we stand in terms of concrete aggregation procedures.

2 Agenda, aggregation rules, and examples

I now introduce the framework, following List and Pettit (2002) and Dietrich (2007).2 We consider a set ofn(≥2) individuals, denotedN ={1, ..., n}. They need to decide which of certain interconnected propositions to ‘believe’ or ‘accept’. The set of propositions under consideration — the agenda — is closed under negation, which ensures that whenever, say,

‘it rains’ is a candidate for belief, so is ‘it does not rain’. The agenda is thus a (disjoint) union of binary ‘issues’ {p,¬p}involving a proposition and its negation. Rationally, ex- actly one proposition from each issue is accepted, and this in accordance with the logical interconnections. Formally, the agenda is simply an arbitrary set X (whose elements we call ‘propositions’) which is

• closed under negation: for every propositionpinX there is a specified proposition denoted¬p(‘notp’) inX such that¬p=p=¬¬p(i.e., such thatX is partitioned into binary issues{p,¬p});

• endowed with logical interconnections: there is a specification of which subsets ofX are ‘consistent’, i.e., formally, there is a systemC of subsets called ‘consistent’.

A ‘judgment set’ A⊆ X is complete if it contains a member of each pair p,¬p∈ X, and (fully) rational if it is complete and consistent. The set of all rational judgment sets is denote byD.3

2To be precise, I use a slimmer variant of their models: I do not explicitly introduce the logicLin which propositions are formed.

3Our notion of an ‘agenda’ is very general. The propositions inXtypically represent what an agent may or may not believe; but alternatively, they could represent arbitrary attributes which an agent may or may not possess such as the attribute of being rich (in which case ‘judgment sets’ are in fact ‘attribute

(5)

As usual in the theory, we assume that the consistency notion is regular. Regularity can be expressed by three conditions: no set{p,¬p}is consistent (C1, ‘self-entailment’); subsets of consistent sets are consistent (C2, ‘monotonicity’); ∅is consistent and each consistent set can be extended to a complete and consistent set (C3, ‘completability’). Equivalently, regularity can be expressed by a single condition: C = {C ⊆ A : A ∈ D} = ∅, i.e., the consistent sets are precisely the subsets of rational sets. The systems D and C are thus interdefinable, so that, given regularity, we could start from D instead of C as the primitive.4

Further, let X be finite. Notationally, a judgment set A ⊆ X is often abbreviated by concatenating its members in any order (so, p¬q¬r is short for {p,¬q,¬r}); and the negation-closure of a setY ⊆Xis denoted

Y± ≡ {p,¬p:p∈Y}.

I now give two standard examples, to which I shall repeatedly refer.

Example 1: the standard ‘doctrinal paradox agenda’. The agenda is X={p, q, r}±.

Logical interconnections are defined relative to the external constraint r↔(p∧q). So, D={pqr, p¬q¬r,¬pq¬r,¬p¬q¬r}.

Example 2: the preference agenda. For an arbitrary, finite set of alternatives K, the preference agenda is defined as

X=XK={xP y:x, y∈K, x=y},

where the negation of a proposition xP y is of course ¬xP y = yP x, and where logical interconnections are defined relative to the usual conditions of transitivity, asymmetry and connectedness, which define astrict linear order. Formally, to each binary relation≻over K uniquely corresponds a judgment set, denotedA={xP y∈X:x≻y}, and the set of all rational judgment sets is

D={A: ≻ is a strict linear order overK}.

A (multi-valued) aggregation rule is a correspondence F which to every profile of

‘individual’ judgment sets (A1, ..., An) (from some domain, usually Dn) assigns a set

sets’). The propositions could be thought of for instance as being syntactic objects (logical expressions) or semantic objects (e.g., sets of worlds). It is often natural to regard the agendaXas a subset of a logic Lfrom which it inherits the negation operator and the logical interconnections. This logic is general: it could for instance be standard propositional logic, standard predicate logic, or various modal or conditional logics (see Dietrich 2007).

4Instead of starting from the system of consistent setsCsatisfying C1-C3 and deriving the systemDof rational judgment sets, we could equivalently have started fromD(any non-empty system of sets containing exactly one member from each pair p,¬pX) and derived the system C:=A∈D{C :C A}(which then automatically satisfies C1-C3). So, in algebraic terms, the agenda is definable either as the structure (X,¬,C)or, equivalently, as the structure(X,¬,D). A future challenge is to relax the conditions C1-C3 by studying, e.g., judgment aggregation in non-monotonic logics (in which caseCmust be the primitive).

(6)

F(A1, ..., An) of ‘collective’ judgment sets. Typically, the output F(A1, ..., An) is a sin- gleton set {C}, in which case we identify this set withC and writeF(A1, ..., An) =C. If F(A1, ..., An)contains more than one judgment set, there is a ‘tie’ between these judgment sets. An aggregation rule is called single-valued or tie-free if it always generates a single judgment set. A standard (single-valued) aggregation rule ismajority rule; it is given by

F(A1, ..., An) ={p∈X:p∈Ai for more than half of the individualsi}

and generates inconsistent collective judgment sets for many agendas and profiles. If both individual and collective judgment sets are rational (i.e., inD), the aggregation rule defines a correspondencesDn⇒D, and in the case of single-valuedness a functionDn→ D.5

3 Scoring rules

Scoring rules are particular judgment aggregation rules, defined on the basis of a so-called scoring function. A scoring function — or simply ascoring — is a functions:X× D →R which to each proposition pand rational judgment set A assigns a numbersA(p), called the score of p given A and measuring how p performs (‘scores’) from the perspective of holding judgment setA. As an elementary example, so-calledsimple scoring is given by:

sA(p) = 1 ifp∈A

0 ifp∈A, (1)

so that all accepted propositions score 1, whereas all rejected propositions score 0. This and many other scorings will be analysed. Let us think of the score of asetof propositions as the sum of the scores of its members. So, the scoringsis extended to a function which (given the agent’s judgment setA∈ D) assigns to each set C⊆X the score

sA(C)≡

p∈C

sA(p).

A scoringsgives rise to an aggregation rule, called thescoring rule w.r.t. sand denoted Fs. Given a profile (A1, ..., An) ∈ Dn, this rule determines the collective judgments by selecting the rational judgment set(s) with the highest sum-total score across all judgments and all individuals:

Fs(A1, ..., An) = judgment set(s) inDwith highest total score

= argmaxC∈D

p∈C,i∈N

sAi(p) = argmaxC∈D

i∈N

sAi(C).

By a scoring rule simpliciter we of course mean an aggregation rule which is a scoring rule w.r.t. some scoring. Different scorings s and s can generate the same scoring rule Fs=Fs, in which case they are calledequivalent. For instance,sis equivalent tos= 2s.6

5More generally, dropping the requirement of collective rationality, we have a correspondenceDn2X, where2Xis the set ofalljudgment sets, rational or not. As usual, I write ‘’ instead of ‘→’ to indicate amulti-function.

6More generally, certain increasing transformations have no effect. As one may show, scoringssands are equivalent (i.e.,Fs=Fs) whenever there are coefficientsa >0andbpR(pX) withbp=b¬pfor allpXsuch thatsis given bysA(p) =asA(p) +bp.

(7)

3.1 Simple scoring and the Hamming rule

We first consider the most elementary definition of scoring, namely simple scoring (1).

Table 2 illustrates the corresponding scoring ruleFsfor the case of the agenda and profile of our doctrinal paradox example. The entries in Table 2 are derived as follows. First, enter

Score of...

p ¬p q ¬q r ¬r pqr p¬q¬r ¬pq¬r ¬p¬q¬r

Indiv. 1 (pqr) 1 0 1 0 1 0 3 1 1 0

Indiv. 2 (p¬q¬r) 1 0 0 1 0 1 1 3 1 2

Indiv. 3 (¬pq¬r) 0 1 1 0 0 1 1 1 3 2

Group 2 1 2 1 1 2 5* 5* 5* 4

Table 2: Simple scoring (1) for the doctrinal paradox agenda and profile

the score of each proposition (p,¬p, q, ...) from each individual (1, 2 and 3). Second, enter each individual’s score of each judgment set by taking the row-wise sum. For instance, individual 1’s score ofpqris1 + 1 + 1 = 3, and his score of p¬q¬ris1 + 0 + 0 = 1. Third, enter the group’s score of each proposition by taking the column-wise sum. For instance, the group’s score of pis1 + 1 + 0 = 2. Finally, enter the group’s score of each judgment set, by taking either a vertical or a horizontal sum (the two give the same result), and add a star ‘*’ in the field(s) with maximal score to indicate the winning judgment set(s).

For instance, the group’s score of pqr using a vertical sum is 3 + 1 + 1 = 5, and using a horizontal sum it is2 + 2 + 1 = 5. Since the judgment setspqr,p¬q¬rand¬pq¬rall have maximal group score, the scoring rule delivers a tie:

F(A1, A2, A3) ={pqr, p¬q¬r,¬pq¬r}.

This is a tie between the premise-based outcome pqr and the conclusion-based outcomes p¬q¬rand¬pq¬r. Were we to add more individuals, the tie would presumably be broken in one way or the other. In large groups, ties are a rare coincidence.

To link simple scoring to distance-based aggregation, suppose we measure the distance between two rational judgment sets by using some distance function (‘metric’)doverD.7 The most common example is Hamming distance d=dHam, defined as follows (where by a ‘judgment reversal’ I mean the replacement of an accepted proposition by its negation):

dHam(A, B) = number of judgment reversals needed to transformA intoB

= |A\B|=|B\A|= 1

2|A△B|.

For instance, the Hamming-distance between pqr and p¬q¬r (for our doctrinal paradox agenda) is 2.

Now the distance-based rule w.r.t. distance d is the aggregation rule Fd which for any profile (A1, ..., An)∈ Dn determines the collective judgment set(s) by minimizing the sum-total distance to the individual judgment sets:

Fd(A1, ..., An) = judgment set(s) inDwith minimal sum-distance to the profile

= argminC∈D

i∈N

d(C, Ai).

7A distance function ormetric overDis a function d:D × D →[0,∞)satisfying three conditions:

for all A, B, C∈ D, (i)d(A, B) = 0A=B, (ii) d(A, B) =d(B, A)(‘symmetry’), and (iii)d(A, C) d(A, B) +d(B, C)(‘triangle inequality’).

(8)

The most popular example, Hamming ruleFdH a m, can be characterized as a scoring rule:

Proposition 1 The simple scoring rule is the Hamming rule.

3.2 Classical scoring rules for preference aggregation

I now show that our scoring rules generalize the classical scoring rules of preference ag- gregation theory. Consider the preference agenda X for a given set of alternatives K of finite size k. Classical scoring rules (such as Borda rule) are defined by assigning scores to alternatives inK, not to propositionsxP yinX. Given a strict linear order≻overK, each alternativex∈K is assigned a scoreSCO(x)∈R. The most popular example is of course Borda scoring, for which the highest ranked alternative in K scoresk, the second- highest k−1, the third-highest k−2, ..., and the lowest 1. Given a profile (≻1, ...,≻n) of individual preferences (strict linear orders), the collective ranks the alternatives x∈X according to their sum-total score i∈NSCOi(x). To translate this into the judgment aggregation formalism, recall that each strict linear order ≻over K uniquely corresponds to a rational judgment set A∈ D (given by xP y∈A ⇔x≻y); we may therefore write SCOA(x)instead of SCO(x), and view the classical scoringSCO as a function of(x, A) inK×D. Formally, I define aclassical scoring as an arbitrary functionSCO:K×D →R, and theclassical scoring rule w.r.t. it as the judgment aggregation ruleF≡FSCO for the preference agenda which for every profile (A1, ..., An)∈ Dn returns the rational judgment set(s) that rank an alternative xover another y wheneverxhas a higher sum-total score thany:8

F(A1, ..., An) ={C∈ D:C contains allxP y∈Xs.t.

i∈N

SCOAi(x)>

i∈N

SCOAi(y)}. Now, any given classical scoringSCOinduces a scoringsin our (proposition-based) sense.

In fact, there are two canonical (and, as we will see, equivalent) ways to defines: one might define seither by

sA(xP y) =SCOA(x)−SCOA(y), (2) or, if one would like the lowest achievable score to be zero, by

sA(xP y) = max{SCOA(x)−SCOA(y),0}= SCOA(x)−SCOA(y) ifxP y∈A

0 ifxP y∈A

(3) (where the last equality assumes that SCOA(x) > SCOA(y) ⇔ xP y ∈ A for all x, y and A, a property that is so natural that we might have built it into the definition of a

‘classical scoring’ SCO). This allows us to characterize classical scoring rules in terms of proposition-based rather than alternative-based scoring:

8A technical difference between the standard notion of a scoring rule in preference aggregation theory and our judgment-theoretic rendition of it arises when there happen to exist distinct alternatives with identical sum-total score. In such cases, the standard scoring rule returns collectiveindifferences, whereas ourFSCOreturns atiebetweenstrictpreferences. From a formal perspective, however, the two definitions are equivalent, since to any weak order corresponds the set (tie) of all strict linear orders which linearize the weak order by breaking its indifferences (in any cycle-free way). The structural asymmetry between input and output preferences of scoring rules as defined standardly (i.e., the possibility of indifferences at the collective level) may have been one of the obstacles — albeit only a small, mainly psychological one — for importing scoring rules and Borda aggregation into judgment aggregation theory.

(9)

Proposition 2 In the case of the preference agenda (for any finite set of alternatives), every classical scoring rule is a scoring rule, namely one with respect to a scoringsderived from the classical scoring SCO via (2) or via (3).

3.3 Reversal scoring and a Borda rule for judgment aggregation

Given the agent’s judgment set A, let us think of the score of a proposition p ∈X as a measure of how ‘distant’ the negation¬pis fromA; so,pscores high if¬pis far fromA, and low if¬pis contained inA. More precisely, let the score of a propositionpgivenA∈ Dbe the number of judgment reversals needed to rejectp, i.e., the number of propositions inA that must (minimally) be negated in order to obtain a consistent judgment set containing

¬p. So, denoting the judgment set arising fromAby negating the propositions in a subset R⊆AbyA¬R= (A\R)∪ {¬r:r∈R}, so-calledreversal scoring is defined by

sA(p) = number of judgment reversals needed to rejectp (4)

= min

R⊆A:A¬R∈D&p∈A¬R|R|= min

A∈D:p∈A|A\A|= min

A∈D:p∈AdHam(A, A).

For instance, a rejected proposition p∈A scores zero, sinceA itself contains ¬pso that it suffices to negate zero propositions (R = ∅). An accepted proposition p ∈ A scores 1 if A remains consistent by negating p (R = {p}), and scores more than 1 otherwise (R {p}). Table 3 illustrates reversal scoring for our doctrinal paradox example. For instance, individual 1’s judgment set pqr leads to a score of 2 for proposition p, since in order for him to reject phe needs to negate not justp(as¬pqr is inconsistent), but also r (where ¬pq¬ris consistent). The scoring rule delivers a tie between the judgment sets

Score of...

p ¬p q ¬q r ¬r pqr p¬q¬r ¬pq¬r ¬p¬q¬r

Indiv. 1 (pqr) 2 0 2 0 2 0 6 2 2 0

Indiv. 2 (p¬q¬r) 1 0 0 2 0 2 1 5 2 4

Indiv. 3 (¬pq¬r) 0 2 1 0 0 2 1 2 5 4

Group 3 2 3 2 2 4 8 9* 9* 8

Table 3: Reversal scoring (4) for the doctrinal paradox agenda and profile

p¬q¬rand¬pq¬r. This is a tie between two conclusion-based outcomes; the premise-based outcomepqris rejected (unlike for simple scoring in Section 3.1).

The remarkable feature of reversal scoring rule is that it generalizes Borda rule from preference to judgment aggregation. Borda rule is initially only defined for the preference agendaX (for a given finite set of alternatives), namely as the classical scoring rule w.r.t.

Borda scoring; see the last subsection. The key observation is that reversal scoring is intimately linked to Borda scoring:

Remark 1 In the case of the preference agenda (for any finite set of alternatives), reversal scoring sis given by (3) withSCO defined as classical Borda scoring.

Let me sketch the simple argument — it should sound familiar to social choice theorists.

Letsbe reversal scoring,Xthe preference agenda for a set of alternativesKof sizek <∞, andSCOclassical Borda scoring. Consider anyxP y∈XandA∈ D. IfxP y∈X\A, then

(10)

¬xP y=yP x∈A, which impliessA(xP y) = 0, as required by (3). Now supposexP y∈A.

Clearly,SCOA(x)> SCOA(y). Consider the alternatives in the order≻established byA:

xk ≻xk−1≻ · · · ≻x≻ · · · ≻y≻ · · · ≻x1,

where xj is the alternative withSCOA(xj) =j. Step by step, we now movey up in the ranking, where each step consists in raising the position (score) of y by one. Each step corresponds to negating one proposition in A, namely the propositionzP ywhere zis the alternative that is currently being ‘overtaken’ by y. After exactly SCOA(x)−SCOA(y) steps,yhas ‘overtaken’x, i.e.,xP yhas been negated. So,sA(xP y)isat most SCOA(x)− SCOA(y). It isexactly SCOA(x)−SCOA(y), since, as the reader may check, no smaller number of judgment reversals allows yto ‘overtake’xin the ranking.

Remark 1 and Proposition 2 imply that reversal scoring allows us to extend Borda rule to arbitrary judgment aggregation problems:

Proposition 3 The reversal scoring rule generalizes Borda rule, i.e., matches it in the case of the preference agenda (for any finite set of alternatives).

I note that one could use a perfectly equivalent variant of reversal scorings which, in the case of the preference agenda, is related to classical Borda scoringSCOvia (2) instead of (3):

Remark 2 Reversal scorings is equivalent (in terms of the resulting scoring rule) to the scoring s given by

sA(p) =sA(p)−sA(¬p) = sA(p) if p∈A

−sA(¬p) if p∈A,

and in the case of the preference agenda (for any finite set of alternatives) this scoring is given by

sA(xP y) =SCOA(x)−SCOA(y) with SCO defined as classical Borda scoring.

For comparison, I now sketch Zwicker’s (2011) interesting approach to extending Borda rule to judgment aggregation — let me call such an extension a ‘Borda-Zwicker’ rule. The motivation derives from a geometric characterization of Borda preference aggregation ob- tained by Zwicker (1991). Let me write the agenda as X={p1,¬p1, p2,¬p2, ..., pm,¬pm}, wheremis the number of ‘issues’. Each profile gives rise to a vectorv≡(v1, ..., vm)inRm whosejthentryvj is thenet support for pj, i.e., the number of individuals acceptingpj mi- nus the same number for¬pj. Now ifXis the preference agenda for any finite set of alterna- tivesK, then eachpjtakes the formxP yfor certain alternativesx, y∈K. Each preference cycle can be mapped to a vector inRm; for instance, ifp1=xP y,p2=yP zandp3=xP z, then the cycle x ≻ y ≻ z ≻ x becomes the vector (1,1,−1,0, ...,0) ∈ Rm. The linear span of all vectors corresponding to preference cycles defines the so-called ‘cycle space’

Vcycle ⊆Rm, and its orthogonal complement defines the ‘cocycle space’ Vcocycle ⊆Rm. Let vcocycle be the orthogonal projection of v on the cocycle space Vcocycle. Intuitively, vcocyclecontains the ‘consistent’ or ‘acyclic’ part ofv. The upshot is that the Borda out- come can be read off fromvcocyle: for eachpj =xP y, the Borda group preference ranksx

(11)

above (below) yif the jth entry ofvcocyleis positive (negative). Zwicker’s strategy for ex- tending Borda rule to judgment aggregation is to define a subspaceVcycle analogously for agendas other than the preference agenda; one can then again projectvon the orthogonal complement ofVcycleand determine collective ‘Borda’ judgments according to the signs of the entries of this projection. This approach has proved successful for simple agendas, in which there is a natural way to defineVcycle. Whether the approach is viable for general agendas (i.e., whetherVcycle has a useful general definition) seems to be open so far.9

A Borda-Zwicker rule is not just constructed differently from a scoring rule in our sense, but, as I conjecture, it also cannot generally be remodelled as a scoring rule, since most interesting scoring rules use information that goes beyond the information contained in the profile’s ‘net support vector’ v ∈Rm. (Even more does the required information go beyond the projection ofvon the orthogonal complement ofVcycle.)

In summary, there seem to exist two quite different approaches to generalizing Borda aggregation. One approach, taken by Zwicker, seeks to filter out the profile’s ‘inconsistent component’ along the lines of the just-described geometric technique. The other approach, taken here, seeks to retain the principle of score-maximization inherent in Borda aggrega- tion (with scoring now defined at the level of propositions, not alternatives, as these do not exist outside the world of preferences). The normative core of the scoring approach is to use information about someone’s strength of accepting a proposition (as measured by the score), just as Borda preference aggregation uses information about someone’sstrength of preferring one alternative xover another y (as measured by the score of xP y, i.e., the difference between x’s and y’s score). Whether strength or intensity of preference is a permissible or even meaningful concept is a notoriously controversial question; the purely ordinalist approach takes a sceptical stance here. This is where Borda preference aggrega- tion differs from Condorcet’s rule of pairwise majority voting, which uses only the (ordinal) information of whether someone prefers an alternative over another, without attempting to extract strength-of-preference information from that person’s full preference relation.

3.4 A generalization of reversal scoring

Recall that the reversal score of a proposition pcan be characterized as the distance by which one must deviate from the current judgment set in order to rejectp— where ‘distance’

is understood as Hamming-distance. It is natural to also consider other kinds of a distance.

Relative to any given distance functiondover D, one may define a corresponding scoring by

sA(p) = distance by which one must depart fromA to rejectp (5)

= min

A∈D:p∈Ad(A, A).

This provides us with a whole class of scoring rules, all of which are variants of our judgment-theoretic Borda rule. In the special case of the preference agenda, we thus obtain new variants of classical Borda rule.

Interestingly, if we adopt Duddy and Piggins’ (2011) distance function, i.e., ifd(A, A) is the number of minimal consistent modifications needed to transformA intoA,10 then

9One might at first be tempted to generally define Vcycle as the linear span of those vectors which correspond to the agenda’sminimal inconsistent subsets. Unfortunately, this span is often the entire space Rm, an example for this being our doctrinal paradox agenda.

1 0Judgment sets A, B ∈ Dareminimal consistent modifications of each other if the setS =A\Bof

(12)

scoring (5) reduces to simple scoring (1), and so the scoring rule reduces to the Hamming rule by Proposition 1. So, ironically, while Duddy and Piggins had introduced their distance in the different context of distance-based aggregation to develop an alternative to Hamming rule, when we use their distance (instead of Hamming’s) in our context of scoring rules we are led back to Hamming rule.

3.5 Scoring based on logical entrenchment

We now consider scoring rules which explicitly exploit the logical structure of the agenda.

Let us think of the score of a proposition p(∈X) given the judgment setA (∈ D) as the degree to whichpis logically entrenched in the belief systemA, i.e., as the ‘strength’ with whichAentailsp. We measure this strength by the number of ways in whichpis entailed by A, where each ‘way’ is given by a particular judgment subset S ⊆A which entails p, i.e., for which S∪ {¬p}is inconsistent. IfAdoes not contain p, then no judgment subset

— not even the full set A— can entailp; so the strength of entailment (score) ofpis zero.

If A containsp, then pis entailed by the judgment subset{p}, and perhaps also by very different judgment subsets; so the strength of entailment (score) of pis positive and more or less high.

There are different ways to formalise this idea, depending on precisely which of the judgment subsets that entail p are deemed relevant. I now propose four formalizations.

Two of them will once again allow us to generalize Borda rule from preference to judgment aggregation. These generalizations differ from that based on reversal scoring in Section 3.3.

Our first, naive approach is to counteachjudgment subset which entailspas a separate, full-fledged ‘way’ in whichpis entailed. This leads to so-calledentailment scoring, defined by:

sA(p) = number of judgment subsets which entail p (6)

= |{S⊆A:S entailsp}|.

Ifp∈AthensA(p) = 0, while ifp∈AthensA(p)≥2|X|/2−1sincepis entailed by at least all setsS ⊆Awhich containp, i.e., by at least2|A|−1 = 2|X|/2−1 sets. One might object that this definition of scoring involves redundancies, i.e., ‘multiple counting’. Suppose for instancepbelongs toAand is logically independent of all other propositions inA. Thenp is entailed by several subsetsSofA— allS⊆Awhich containp— and yet these entailments are essentially identical since all premises in S other thanpare irrelevant.

I now present three refinements of scoring (6), each of which responds differently to the mentioned redundancy objection. In the first refinement, we count two entailments of p as different only if they have no premise in common. This leads to what I call disjoint- entailment scoring, formally defined by:

sA(p) = number ofmutually disjoint judgment subsets entailingp (7)

= max{m:Ahasm mutually disjoint subsets each entailingp}.

propositions in Awhich need to be negated to transform Ainto B is non-empty and minimal (i.e., A couldn’t have been transformed into a consistent set by negating only a strict non-empty subset ofS). For our doctrinal paradox agenda, the judgment sets pqrandp¬q¬rare minimal consistent modifications of each other, and hence have Duddy-Piggins-distance of 1.

(13)

In the mentioned case where p(∈A) is logically independent of all other propositions in A, we now avoid ‘multiple counting’: sA(p)is only 1, as one cannot find different mutually disjoint judgment subsets entailing p. For our doctrinal paradox agenda and profile, the scoring rule delivers a tie between the two conclusion-based outcomes p¬q¬r and¬pq¬r,

Score of...

p ¬p q ¬q r ¬r pqr p¬q¬r ¬pq¬r ¬p¬q¬r

Indiv. 1 (pqr) 2 0 2 0 2 0 6 2 2 0

Indiv. 2 (p¬q¬r) 1 0 0 2 0 2 1 5 2 4

Indiv. 3 (¬pq¬r) 0 2 1 0 0 2 1 2 5 4

Group 3 2 3 2 2 4 8 9* 9* 8

Table 4: Disjoint-entailment scoring (7) for the doctrinal paradox agenda and profile as illustrated in Table 4. For instance, individual 2 has judgment set p¬q¬r, so that p sores 1 (it is entailed by {p} but by no other disjoint judgment subset), ¬q scores 2 (it is disjointly entailed by {¬q}and {p,¬r}), ¬r scores 2 (it is disjointly entailed by {¬r} and{¬q}), and all rejected propositions score zero (they are not entailed by any judgment subsets).

Disjoint-entailment scoring turns out to match reversal scoring for our doctrinal paradox agenda (check that Tables 3 and 4 coincide), as well as for the preference agenda (as shown later). Is this pure coincidence? The general relationship is that the disjoint-entailment score of a propositionpis alwaysat most the reversal score, as one may show.11

While this refinement of naive entailment scoring (6) avoids ‘multiple counting’ by only counting entailments with mutually disjoint sets of premises, the next two refinements use a different strategy to avoid ‘multiple counting’. The new strategy is to count only those entailments whose sets of premises areminimal— with minimality understood either in the sense that no premises can be removed, or in the sense that no premises can be logically weakened. To begin with the first sense of minimality, I say that a set minimally entails p(∈X) if it entailspbut no strict subset of it entailsp, and I define minimal-entailment scoring by

sA(p) = number of judgment subsets which minimally entailp (8)

= |{S⊆A:S minimally entailsp}|.

If for instance pis contained inA, then{p}minimally entailsp,12 but strict supersets of {p}do not and are therefore not counted. For our doctrinal paradox agenda, this scoring happens to coincide with reversal scoring and disjoint-entailment scoring. Indeed, Table 3 resp. 4 still applies; e.g., for individual 2 with judgment set p¬q¬r, pstill scores 1 (it is minimally entailed only by {p}),¬qstill scores 2 (it is minimally entailed by{¬q}and by {p,¬r}),¬rstill scores 2 (it is minimally entailed by{¬r}and by{¬q}), and all rejected propositions still score zero (they are not minimally entailed by any judgment subsets).

Scoring (8) is certainly appealing. Nonetheless, one might complain that it still al- lows for certain redundancies, albeit of a different kind. Consider the preference agenda with set of alternatives K = {x, y, z, w}, and the judgment set A = {xP y, yP z, zP w,

1 1The reason is that, givenmmutually disjoint judgment subsets which each entailp, the reversal score of p is at least msince one must negate at least one proposition from each of these msets in order to consistently rejectp.

1 2Assuming thatpis not a tautology, i.e., that{¬p}is consistent. (Otherwise,minimally entailsp.)

(14)

xP z, yP w, xP w} (∈ D). The proposition xP w is minimally entailed by the subset S ={xP y, yP z, zP w}. While this entailment is minimal in the (set-theoretic) sense that we cannot remove premises, it is non-minimal in the (logical) sense that we can weaken some of its premises: if we replace xP y and yP z in S by their logical implicationxP z, then we obtain a weaker set of premises S = {xP z, zP w} which still entails xP w. We shall say that S fails to ‘irreducibly’ entail xP w, in spite of minimally entailing it. In general, a set of propositions is calledweaker than another one (which is calledstronger) if the second set entails each member of the first set, but not vice versa. A set S (⊆X) is defined toirreducibly(orlogically minimally) entailpifS entailsp, and moreover there is no subset Y S which can be weakened (i.e., for which there is a weaker set Y ⊆X such that(S\Y)∪Y still entailsp). Each irreducible entailment is a minimal entailment, as is seen by taking Y =∅.13 In the previous example, the set {xP y, yP z, zP w}mini- mally, but not irreducibly entails xP w, and the set {xP z, zP w}irreducibly entailsxP w.

Irreducible-entailment scoring is naturally defined by

sA(p) = number of judgment subsets whichirreducibly entailp (9)

= |{S⊆A:S irreducibly entails p}|.

This scoring matches reversal scoring and both previous scorings in the case of our doc- trinal paradox example: Table 3 resp. 4 still applies. But for many other agendas these scorings all deviate from one another, resulting in different collective judgments. As for the preference agenda, we have already announced the following result:

Proposition 4 Disjoint-entailment scoring (7) and irreducible-entailment scoring (9) match reversal scoring (4) in the case of the preference agenda (for any finite set of alternatives).

Propositions 3 and 4 jointly have an immediate corollary.

Corollary 1 The scoring rules w.r.t. scorings (7) and (9) both generalize Borda rule, i.e., match it in the case of the preference agenda (for any finite set of alternatives).

3.6 Propositionwise scoring and a way to repair quota rules with non-rational outputs

We now consider a special class of scorings: propositionwise scorings. This will allow us to relate scoring rules to the well-known judgment aggregation rules called quota rules — in fact, to ‘repair’ these rules by rendering their outcomes rational across all profiles.

I call scoring s propositionwise if the score of a proposition p ∈ X only depends on whether pis accepted, i.e., if sA(p) =sB(p)wheneverA and B (in D) both containpor both do not containp. Equivalently, scoring is propositionwise just in case for eachp∈X there is a pair of real numberss+(p), s(p)such that

sA(p) = s+(p) for allA∈ Dcontainingp

s(p) for allA∈ Dnot containingp. (10) Intuitively, s+(p) is the score of an accepted proposition p, and s(p) is the score of a rejected propositionp. Typically, of course,s+(p)> s(p). An example is simple scoring:

there, s+(p) = 1ands(p) = 0.

1 3AssumingXcontains no tautology, i.e., nopsuch that{¬p}is inconsistent.

(15)

How do propositionwise scoring rules behave? They derive a propositionp’s sum-total score ‘locally’, i.e., based only on people’s judgments about p. This property stands in obvious analogy to a well-studied axiom on aggregation rules, namely the axiom of propo- sitionwiseorindependentaggregation, which prescribes that the collective judgment about any given proposition p is derived ‘locally’, i.e., again based only on people’s judgments about p. Can we therefore relate propositionwise scoring to independent aggregation?

The paradigmatic independent aggregation rules are the quota rules.14 A quota rule is a (single-valued) aggregation rule which is given by an acceptance threshold mp∈ {1, ..., n} for each propositionp∈X. The quota rule corresponding to the so-calledthreshold family (mp)p∈X is denotedF(mp)p∈X and accepts those propositionspwhich are supported by at leastmpindividuals: for each profile (A1, ..., An)∈ Dn,

F(mp)pX(A1, ..., An) ={p∈X:|{i:p∈Ai}| ≥mp}.

Special cases are unanimity rule (given by mp = n for all p), majority rule (given by the majority threshold mp = ⌈(n+ 1)/2⌉ for all p), and more generally, uniform quota rules (given by a uniform threshold mp ≡ m for all p). A uniform quota rules is also referred to as a supermajority rule ifmexceeds the majority threshold, and a submajority rule if m is below the majority threshold. Note that supermajority rules may generate incomplete collective judgment sets, while submajority rule may accept both members of a pair p,¬p∈X, a drastic form of inconsistency. If one wishes that exactly one member of each pairp,¬p∈X is accepted, the thresholds ofpand¬pshould be ‘complements’ of each other: mp=n+ 1−m¬p.

A non-trivial question is how the acceptance thresholds would have to be set to ensure that the collective judgment set satisfies some given degree of rationality, such as to be (i) consistent, or (ii) deductively closed, or (iii) consistent and deductively closed, or even (iv) fully rational, i.e., inD. These questions have been settled (see Nehring and Puppe 2010a for (iv), and, subsequently, Dietrich and List 2007b for (i)-(iv)). Unfortunately, for many agendas the thresholds would have to be set at ‘extreme’ and normatively unattractive levels. Worse, often no thresholds achieve (iv) (see Nehring and Puppe 2010a). For our doctrinal paradox agendaX={p, q, r}± only the extreme thresholdsmp=mq=mr=n and m¬p =m¬q =m¬r = 1achieve (iv), and for the preference agenda (with more than two alternatives)no thresholds achieve (iv).

Given that quota rules with ‘reasonable’ thresholds typically violate many of the condi- tions (i)-(iv), one may want to depart from ordinary quota rules by modifying (‘repairing’) them so that they always generate rational outputs. This can be done by using proposi- tionwise scoring rules. Given an arbitrary quota rule with threshold family(mp)p∈X, one can specify a propositionwise scoring such that the scoring rule replicates the quota rule whenever the quota rule generates a rational output, while ‘repairing’ the output other- wise. How must we calibrate s+(p) ands(p)in order to achieve this? The idea is that individuals who accept p should contribute a positive score s+(p) > 0, while those who reject p should contribute a negative score s(p) < 0. The absolute sizes of s+(p) and s(p) should be calibrated such that the sum-total score of pbecomes positive (helping the scoring rule to accept p) exactly when the quota rule acceptsp, i.e., when at leastmp

individuals acceptp. Specifically, we set:

sA(p) = s+(p) =n+ 1−mp for allA∈ Dcontainingp

s(p) =−mp for allA∈ Dnot containingp. (11)

1 4They are the only independent rules which are anonymous, monotonic and unanimity-preserving.

(16)

Intuitively, the higher the acceptance thresholdmpis, the smaller the positive contribution s+(p)is and the larger the negative contribution s(p)is (in absolute value); hence, the more individuals accepting p are needed for p’s sum-total score to get positive, and the harder it becomes for the scoring rule to acceptp. This scoring does the intended job:

Proposition 5 For every threshold family(mp)p∈X, the scoring rule w.r.t. scoring (11) matches the quota rule F(mp)pX at all profiles where the quota rule generates rational outputs (and still generates rational outputs at all other profiles).

As an example, consider our doctrinal paradox agenda X = {p, q, r}± with n = 3 individuals, and suppose the quota rule departs only slightly from propositionwise majority voting: all propositionst inX\{¬r}keep a majority threshold ofmt= 2, but¬rreceives a unanimity threshold m¬r = 3. This quota rule manages to never generate logically inconsistent collective judgment sets,15 but does so at the expense of allowing collective incompleteness. Indeed, for our example profile, the quota rule returns the collective judgment setpq, which is silent on the choice betweenrnor¬r. As illustrated in Table 5, the scoring rule w.r.t. (11) restores collective rationality by leading to the premise-based

Score of...

p ¬p q ¬q r ¬r pqr p¬q¬r ¬pq¬r ¬p¬q¬r

Indiv. 1 (pqr) 2 -2 2 -2 2 -3 6 -3 -3 -7

Indiv. 2 (p¬q¬r) 2 -2 -2 2 -2 1 -2 5 -3 1

Indiv. 3 (¬pq¬r) -2 2 2 -2 -2 1 -2 -3 5 1

Group 2 -2 2 -2 -2 -1 2* -1 -1 -5

Table 5: Scoring (11) for the doctrinal paradox agenda and profile

outcomepqr. To read the table, note that scoring (11) is given bys+(t) = 2ands(t) =−2 for alltinX\{¬r},s+(¬r) = 1ands(¬r) =−3.

How does our scoring rule ‘repair’ those special quota rules which use a uniform thresh- old m≡mp(p∈X), such as majority rule?

Remark 3 For a uniform threshold m ≡mp, the scoring rule w.r.t. scoring (11) is the Hamming rule, or equivalently, the simple scoring rule.

This remark follows from Proposition 1 and the fact that, for a uniform threshold m≡mp, scoring (11) is equivalent to simple scoring by footnote 6.

Finally, I note that the scoring rules w.r.t. (11) is not the only scoring rule which can

‘repair’ the quota ruleF(mp)p∈X — though it might be the most plausible one, as long as we do not wish to introduce additional parameters. If, however, we are prepared to introduce additional parameters, scoring (11) can be generalized: for each p ∈ X let αp > 0be a coefficient measuring how important it is that the scoring rule is faithful to the quota rule’s collective judgment onp; and let scoring be defined by

sA(p) = s+(p) =αp(n+ 1−mp) ifp∈A

s(p) =−αpmp ifp∈A. (12)

1 5This follows from Nehring and Puppe’s (2010)intersection property, generalized to possibly incomplete collective judgment sets (Dietrich and List 2007b).

(17)

The earlier scoring (11) is obviously a special case in which all αp are 1. Proposition 5 still holds for this generalized kind of propositionwise scoring. The scoring rule will tend to match the quota rule on propositionspwith high importance coefficientαp, while modifying (‘repairing’) the quota rule at propositionspwith lowαp.

3.7 Premise- and conclusion-based aggregation

I have just mentioned the possibility of a differential treatment of propositions when ‘re- pairing’ a quota rule. This possibility is particularly salient in the popular context of premise- or conclusion-based aggregation.16 One may indeed view the classical premise- and conclusion-based rules as two (rival) ways of repairing the simplest of all quota rules — majority rule — by privileging certain propositions over others, namely premise propositions or conclusion propositions, respectively.

Let me put this precisely. Consider majority voting, i.e., the quota rule with a uniform majority threshold m ≡mp (the smallest integer above n/2). To restore collective ratio- nality, we again endow each proposition p∈X with a ‘coefficient of importance’, but now let this coefficient be determined by whetherphas a ‘premise’ or ‘conclusion’ status. For- mally, suppose the agenda is partitioned into two negation-closed sets, the setPof ‘premise propositions’ and the set X\P of ‘conclusion propositions’. In the case of our doctrinal paradox agendaX={p, q, r}±, we haveP={p, q}±. Each premise propositionp∈P has the importance coefficient αp ≡ αpremise, and each conclusion propositionp ∈ X\P has the importance coefficient αp ≡αconclusion, for fixed parameters αpremise, αconclusion ≥ 0.

In this scenario, the scoring (12) becomes equivalent (by footnote 6) to the scoring given by

sA(p) =



αpremise for accepted premise propositionsp∈A∩P αconclusion for accepted conclusion propositionsp∈A\P 0 for rejected propositionsp∈A.

(13) By calibrating the two importance coefficients, we can influence the relative weights of premises and conclusions. If we givefar moreimportance to premise propositions (αpremise≫ αcoclusion) or to conclusion propositions (αcoclusion≫αpremise), the scoring rule reduces to the premise- or conclusion-based rule, respectively. To substantiate this claim, one needs to define both rules. For simplicity, I restrict attention to our doctrinal paradox agenda X ={p, q, r}± withP ={p, q}± (though more generalX and P could be considered17).

In this case, assuming for simplicity that the group size nis odd,

• thepremise-based rule is the aggregation rule which for each profile in Dn delivers the (unique) judgment set in D containing each premise proposition accepted by a majority;

• theconclusion-based rule is the aggregation rule which for each profile inDndelivers the judgment set (or sets) inDcontaining the conclusion proposition accepted by a majority.18

These two rules have the following characterizations as scoring rules:

1 6See for instance List (2004), Dietrich and Mongin (2010) and Nehring and Puppe (2010b).

1 7Our analysis generalizes easily to anyXandP such that (i) the premise propositions inPare logically independent, and (ii) complete judgments across the premise propositions in P uniquely determine the judgments on the conclusion propositions inX\P.

1 8In the literature, the conclusion-based procedure is usually taken to besilenton the premises, i.e., to return an incomplete judgment set not in D. I have replaced this silence by a tie between all compatible judgments on the premise propositions.

(18)

Remark 4 For our doctrinal paradox agendaX={p, q, r}± with set of premise proposi- tions P={p, q}±, and for an odd group size, the scoring rule w.r.t. scoring (13) is

• the premise-based rule if and only if αpremise>(n−2)αconclusion,

• the conclusion-based rule if and only ifαconclusion> αpremise= 0.

This result lets premise- and conclusion-based aggregation appear in a rather ex- treme light: each rule is based on somewhat unequal importance coefficients αpremise and αconclusion, deeming one type of proposition to be overwhelmingly more important than the other. It might therefore be interesting to consider more equilibrated values of the importance coefficients, so as to achieve a compromise between democracy at the premise level and democracy at the conclusion level.

4 Set scoring rules: assigning scores to entire judgment sets

An interesting generalization of scoring rules is obtained by assigning scores directly to entire judgment sets rather than single propositions. Aset scoring function— or simplyset scoring — is a functionσwhich to every pair of rational judgment setsC andA assigns a real numberσA(C), thescore ofCgivenA, which measures how wellCperforms (‘scores’) from the perspective of holding the judgment setA. Formally,σ:D × D →R. The most elementary example, to be callednaive set scoring, is given by

σA(C) = 1 ifC=A

0 ifC=A. (14)

Any set scoring σ gives rise to an aggregation rule Fσ, the set scoring rule (or general- ized scoring rule) w.r.t. σ, which for each profile (A1, ..., An)∈ Dn selects the collective judgment set(s) C inDhaving maximal sum-total score across individuals:

Fσ(A1, ..., An) = argmaxC∈D

i∈N

σAi(C).

An aggregation rule is a set scoring rule simpliciter if it is the set scoring rule w.r.t. to some set scoringσ. Set scoring rules generalize ordinary scoring rules, since to any ordinary scoringscorresponds a set scoringσ, given by

σA(C)≡

p∈C

sA(p),

and the ordinary scoring rule w.r.t. scoincides with the set scoring rule w.r.t. σ.

4.1 Naive set scoring and plurality voting

Plurality rule is the aggregation ruleF which for every profile (A1, ..., An)∈ Dn declares the most often submitted judgment set(s) as the collective judgment set(s):

F(A1, ..., An) = most frequently submitted judgment set(s)

= argmaxC∈D|{i:Ai=C}|.

(19)

This rule is of course normatively questionable;19 but it deserves our attention, if only because of its simplicity and the recognized importance of plurality voting in social choice theory more broadly. Plurality rule can be construed as a set scoring rule:

Remark 5 The naive set scoring rule is plurality rule.

4.2 Distance-based set scoring

Set scoring rules generalize distance-based aggregation. Given an arbitrary distance func- tion d over D (not necessarily the Hamming-distance), all that is needed is to consider what I call distance-based set scoring, defined by

σA(C) =−d(C, A). (15)

So, C scores high if it is close to the judgment set held, A. This renders sum-score- maximization equivalent to sum-distance-minimization:

Remark 6 For every given distance function overD, the distance-based set scoring rule is the distance-based rule.

So, all distance-based rules can be modelled as set scoring rules (but not vice versa20).

As an example, consider the so-called discrete distance,21 defined by d(A, B) = 0 ifA=B

1 ifA=B.

Here, distance-based set scoring (15) is equivalent to naive set scoring (14), since the two differ only by a constant (of one). So, joining Remarks 5 and 6, we may view plurality rule either as the naive set scoring rule or as the discrete-distance-based rule.

4.3 Approximating the ‘average voter’

Given an ordinary scoring s, we have so far aimed for collective judgments with high total score. But this is not the only plausible aim or approach. We now turn to an altogether different approach. Rather than using s to assign scores only from each individual’s per- spective, we now care about how propositions score under the collective judgment set.

Instead of wanting the collective judgments to get highest total score from individuals, we now want them to resemble an ‘average individual’s judgments’ in the sense that the collective judgments should lead (approximately) to the same scores of propositions as the individual judgments do on average. In short, any propositionp’s collective score should be (approximately) p’s average individual score. This approach has its own, rather different intuitive appeal. But is it really totally different? As will turn out, aggregation rules which

1 9It ignores the internal structure of judgment sets, hence ‘throws away’ much information.

2 0In trying to re-model an arbitrary set scoring ruleFσ as a distance-based rule, one might be tempted to define the ‘distance’ betweenAandBasdσ(A, B) :=σA(A)−σA(B). Ifdσturns out to define a proper distance function (see fn. 7), then we obtain a distance-based ruleFdσ, which coincides with the set scoring ruleFσ. But for many plausible set scoringsσ,dσhas little in common with a distance function, violating up to all three axioms, notably symmetry and the triangle inequality.

2 1This metric derives its name from the fact that it induces the discrete topology on whatever set it is defined on (such asRinstead ofD).

Referenzen

ÄHNLICHE DOKUMENTE

In response to a parametric manipulation of prior motor-goal probability in a rule-based action selection task, monkey behavior showed decreased error rates (ER), faster reaction

In the proof of the Inverse Function Theorem 3.26 one encounters a relatively typical situation: The problem is reduced to finding a fixed point of a self-map, and then a restriction

Mit anderen Worten bedeutet das: wenn der Schutzbereich der BJR einmal eröffnet ist, ist eine richterliche Überprüfung der unternehmerischen Entscheidung der directors oder

In the special case of the classical relevance notion, the two axioms reduce to their classical counterparts, and the theorems reduce to familiar results such as the Arrow-like

We predicted that participants with higher working memory capacity would make more accurate judgments in the linear task, whereas those with better episodic

Since we consider choice rules as the result of some explicit non-binary choice procedure, we provide conditions based on the non-binary choice liter- ature which lead to the

The paradigm underlying our scoring rules – i.e., the maximization of total score of collective judgments – di¤ers from standard paradigms in judgment aggregation, such as the

Quantum strategies have been successfully applied in game the- ory for years. However, as a reverse problem of game theory, the theory of mechanism design is ignored by physicists.