• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

A Prototype Selection Committee Decision Analysis and Support System, SCDAS: Theoretical Background and Computer Implementation

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Aktie "A Prototype Selection Committee Decision Analysis and Support System, SCDAS: Theoretical Background and Computer Implementation"

Copied!
16
0
0

Wird geladen.... (Jetzt Volltext ansehen)

Volltext

(1)

W O R K I N G P A P E R

A PROTOTYPE SELECTIOZJ C O M M I m DEC1SIO:J 1 AIGLYSIS PJD SUPPORT SYSTEN, SC3lL?iS :

'IIIEORETICAL EACI<GROTJlJ;)

A!

COQUTER IMPIXFECJTATIOiJ

A. & w a n d o w s k i S

.

Johnson A. T d i e r z b i z l ~ i

June 1935 LIP-36-337

I n t e r n a t i o n a l I n s t i t u t e for Applied Systems Analysis

(2)

NOT FOR QUOTATION WITHOUT THE PERMISSION OF THE AUTHORS

A PROTOTYPE SEXZXXION COMkUlTEZ DECISION ANALZS'E AND SUPPORT SETEX. SCDAS:

THEORETICAL BACKGROUND AND COMPUTER -ATION

A n d r z e j L e w a d m s k i S a r a h Johnson A n d r z e j W i e n b t c k i

June 1986 WP-86-27

Working P a p e r s a r e interim r e p o r t s on work of the International Institute f o r Applied Systems Analysis and have received only limited review. Views o r opinions expressed herein do not necessarily r e p r e s e n t those of t h e Institute o r of its National Member Organizations.

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLID SYSEMS ANALYSIS 2361 Laxenburg. Austria

(3)

Foreword

One of t h e important problems in decision analysis r e l a t e d t o t h e situation, where t h e committee (group of decision makers) h a s t o s e l e c t t h e b e s t a l t e r n a t i v e from a given, finite set. In t h e most cases, t h e a l t e r n a t i v e s are evaluated on t h e basis of s e v e r a l quality factors. In t h e p a p e r , t h e a u t h o r s p r e s e n t t h e new ap- p r o a c h , based on t h e principle of s a t i s f a c t o r y decision making. This a p p r o a c h en- s u r e s p r o p e r structuralization of t h e decision p r o c e s s and allows p r o p e r balance of opinion of t h e group member. The experimental decision s u p p o r t system SCDAS w a s developed t o test t h i s a p p r o a c h .

The r e s e a r c h i s a r e s u l t of cooperative work between t h e System and Decision Sciences Program and t h e Institute of Automatic Control in Warsaw, done within t h e scientific agreement between IIASA and t h e Polish Academy of Sciences. S a r a h Johnson took p a r t in t h e p r o j e c t during h e r participation in t h e YSSP program at IIASA.

Alexander B. Kurzhanski Chairman

System and Decision Sciences Program

(4)

A PROTOTYPE SELECXION COMMI'ITEE DECISION ANALYSIS AND SUPPORT SICSTEM.

SCDAS:

THEORETICAL BACKGROUND

AND

COMPUTER JMPLEMENTATION

* * *

A n d r z e j L e w a n d o w s k i , S a r a h ~ o h n s o n * a n d A n d r z e j W i e r z b i c k i

*

International Institute f o r Applied Systems Analysis, Laxenburg ,Austria

**

Institute of Automatic Control, University of Warsaw, Warsaw, Poland

1. MTRODUCTION

Many major decisions in public and p r i v a t e a r e n a s are delegated to commit- tees. The institution of a committee, though i t h a s many shortcomings, remains a n important a s p e c t of many decision p r o c e s s e s ; t h e p r o c e s s of committee decision- making must t h e r e f o r e b e improved. A s a r e s u l t of p e r s o n a l e x p e r i e n c e s with com- mittees, t h e a u t h o r s have developed a p r o c e d u r a l concept and a n automated aid f o r decision-making by committee, aimed in p a r t i c u l a r at a committee c h a r g e d with t h e t a s k of selecting from a finite set of alternatives.

The t h e o r e t i c a l framework f o r t h e automated system called "SCDAS" ( f o r Selection Committee Decision Analysis and S u p p o r t system) follows t h e concept developed by Johnson (1984). The multi-person decision s u p p o r t system i s based on t h e construction of a n order-consistent achievement function (Wierzbicki, 1985) which i s used as a multivariable c a r d i n a l utility function and depends explicitly on t h e contextual information supplied by t h e u s e r s . The system d e s c r i b e d c a n b e ap- plied to a wide spectrum of decision problems and s e r v e s as a p r o c e s s o r of infor- mation a b o u t p r e f e r e n c e s and a l t e r n a t i v e s t h a t guides t h e committee. The comput- er implementation i s non-procedural in t h a t a menu format allows e n t r y a n d re- e n t r y into many s t a g e s of t h e p r o c e s s , t h u s allowing a g r e a t deal of p r o c e d u r a l flexibility. Additionally, a r i c h g r a p h i c r e p r e s e n t a t i o n h a s proven quite u s e r - friendly on t h e basis of s e v e r a l empirical tests.

The organization of t h e p a p e r i s as follows. F i r s t , t h e t h e o r e t i c a l background and t e c h n i c a l a s p e c t s of t h e system are discussed. A section devoted to a discus- sion of t h e p r o c e d u r a l framework follows. A t u t o r i a l example of t h e selection of a candidate by a r e c r u i t i n g committee i s used throughout f o r i l l u s t r a t i v e purposes.

The final section p r e s e n t s in brief t h e computer implementation of SCDAS and t h e limitations and f u r t h e r extensions of t h e system, t h e primary o n e being t h e explicit inclusion of uncertainty in t h e evaluation of a l t e r n a t i v e s .

(5)

2. THEORETICAL BACKGROUND

The problem of selecting one a l t e r n a t i v e from a finite set of a l t e r n a t i v e s p r e s e n t e d t o a committee i s one of t h e most basic and classical decision problems and h a s received much attention in t h e decision-theoretical l i t e r a t u r e . T h e r e are many detailed v a r i a n t s of such a problem; h e r e , w e consider t h e following a b s t r a c t variant:

A committee consists of s e v e r a l members (denoted h e r e by k

=

1.

...,

K); e a c h

member c a n have e i t h e r equal o r different v o t i n g power (denoted h e r e by a voting power coefficient v ( k ) ) , specified a p r i o r i by t h e committee c h a r t e r . In addition t o t h e committee s t r u c t u r e , t h e committee c h a r t e r might specify t h e p u r p o s e of t h e committee's work, f u r t h e r p r o c e d u r a l details, e t c .

The problem faced by t h e committee i s t o jointly r a n k o r s e l e c t one o r a f e w from a set of available d e c i s i o n a l t e r n a t i v e s (these might b e candidates f o r a job, proposals f o r R&D p r o j e c t s , a l t e r n a t i v e t r a n s p o r t a t i o n r o u t e s , proposed s i t e s of a n industrial facility, a l t e r n a t i v e computer systems, etc.). The list of a l t e r n a t i v e s need not b e complete at t h e beginning of t h e committee's work; during t h e decision-making p r o c e s s , new a l t e r n a t i v e s may b e g e n e r a t e d and subsequently evaluated.

Evaluation of a l t e r n a t i v e s i s performed by t h e committee by f i r s t specifying d e c i s i o n a t t r i b u t e s (such as a candidate's age, e x p e r i e n c e , professional r e p u t a - tion, e t c . ) and t h e n assessing e a c h a l t e r n a t i v e with r e s p e c t t o e a c h of t h e s e a t t r i - butes. The l i s t of decision a t t r i b u t e s (denoted by j

=

I,.. ., J) might b e specified in t h e committee's c h a r t e r o r decided upon by t h e committee. In any c a s e , decision a t t r i b u t e s must b e specified b e f o r e a l t e r n a t i v e s c a n be evaluated and compared.

Each a l t e r n a t i v e (denoted by i

=

1 , . . . , I ) must b e evaluated by t h e committee o r i t s individual members. The problem consists of proposing a d e c i s i o n process which t o g e t h e r with assessment of various a t t r i b u t e s of t h e a l t e r n a t i v e s and aggregation of evaluations a c r o s s both a t t r i b u t e s and committee members, leads t o a final ranking o r selection of a n alternative@) in a way t h a t i s rational, under- standable and a c c e p t a b l e t o t h e committee members.

S e v e r a l a p p r o a c h e s t o t h i s problem have been developed; most of them a r e based on t h e classical multi-attribute utility t h e o r y ( s e e e.g. Keeney and Raiffa, 1976), but t h e r e are a l s o a l t e r n a t i v e a p p r o a c h e s , such as t h e analytical h i e r a r c h y of Saaty (1982) o r t h e o r d e r i n g s of Roy (1971). Some of t h e s e a p p r o a c h e s have been a l s o implemented as microcomputer-based decision s u p p o r t systems: a n in- t e r e s t i n g implementation i s t h a t of analytical h i e r a r c h y (EXPERT CHOICE, 1983) o r t h e non-procedural package DEMOS (1982) used f o r probabilistic evaluation of al- t e r n a t i v e s . Another commercially available implementation (LIGHTYEAR. 1984), based on utility t h e o r y and weighting coefficients specified by t h e u s e r , employs a r a t h e r primitive decision p r o c e s s and i s r e s t r i c t e d t o only one u s e r , hence i t i s not applicable in committee decisions.

Most of t h e s e a p p r o a c h e s r e l y on e i t h e r user-supplied rankings of a t t r i b u t e s and a l t e r n a t i v e s f o r e a c h a t t r i b u t e , pairwise comparisons of alternatives, o r some uncertainty equivalence principle (e.g. comparisons t o a lottery). The available assembly of a l t e r n a t i v e s plays a n important r o l e when establishing t h e principles of t h e decision. Such decision p r o c e s s e s will b e called a l t e r n a t i v e - l e d . An attempt t o establish decision principles independently of available a l t e r n a t i v e s is possible when specifying weighting coefficients by t h e u s e r ; but in addition t o t h e problem of having t o specify utility functions o r explicit weighting functions f o r t h e multi- ple a t t r i b u t e s , weighting coefficients c a n b e reasonably i n t e r p r e t e d only locally, when t h e available a l t e r n a t i v e s do not d i f f e r much in all of t h e a t t r i b u t e s . When t h e available a l t e r n a t i v e s d i f f e r significantly in some a t t r i b u t e s . t h e approximate

(6)

linearity of t h e u s e r ' s utility function i s a questionable assumption.

An easily i n t e r p r e t a b l e outline of decision principles t h a t are independent of available a l t e r n a t i v e s i s possible when requiring e a c h member t o specify a s p i r a - tion and ( o r ) r e s e r v a t i o n levels f o r t h e evaluation of e a c h a t t r i b u t e . Such a pro- c e s s will b e called aspiration-Led. The concept of a n aspiration level i s essential f o r t h e s a t i s f i c i n g f r a m e w o r k of decision-making (Simon, 1958). where i t i s as- sumed t h a t as soon as a n a l t e r n a t i v e i s discovered t h a t meets aspiration levels f o r all a t t r i b u t e s , t h e s e a r c h f o r a l t e r n a t i v e s is terminated and t h e choice i s made.

However, w e do not a d h e r e h e r e t o t h e s t r i c t l y satisficing framework: aspiration levels are used r a t h e r in t h e construction of a n approximate multivariable cardi- nal utility function t h a t i s f u r t h e r a v e r a g e d and maximized in t h e system. This ap- p r o a c h i s called q u a s i s a t i s f i c i n g ( s e e Wierzbicki, 1985).

The r e s e r v a t i o n level r e p r e s e n t s a minimum a c c e p t a b l e level f o r e a c h a t t r i - bute (e.g. minimum 5 y e a r s ' e x p e r i e n c e f o r t h e position), whereas a n a s p i r a t i o n level r e f l e c t s a h i g h e r d e s i r e d level of e x p e r t i s e . If a n a l t e r n a t i v e i s evaluated below t h e r e s e r v a t i o n level on even one a t t r i b u t e , i t i s considered unacceptable, and if i t i s evaluated at l e a s t equal t o aspiration levels f o r a l l a t t r i b u t e s , i t i s con- sidered highly desirable. Nonlinear approximations of utility functions based on aspiration (reservation) levels supplied by t h e u s e r a r e called (order-consistent, o r o r d e r - p r e s e r v i n g and r e p r e s e n t i n g ) achievement f u n c t i o n s and have been stu- died in detail by Wierzbicki (1982, 1985). Johnson (1984) h a s worked out a concept f o r a selection committee decision analysis and s u p p o r t system based on committee-supplied aspiration levels and t h e use of achievement functions f o r both alternative-led and aspiration-led v a r i a n t s of t h e decision p r o c e s s ; however, only t h e latter i s chosen h e r e f o r implementation.

2-1. Setting and discussing aspirations

An aspiration-led decision p r o c e s s h a s s e v e r a l advantages. Most judgmental decision p r o c e s s e s r e q u i r e a choice of (and, in a committee, agreement upon) s c a l e s of evaluation f o r e a c h decision a t t r i b u t e

.

The s c a l e s are often qualitative, such as unacceptable, bad, a c c e p t a b l e , good. v e r y good, excellent, though they can b e transformed into quantitative s c a l e s f o r computational purposes. When asked t o specify a n c h o r p o i n t s (aspiration and r e s e r v a t i o n levels) on t h e s e s c a l e s at a n e a r l y s t a g e of t h e decision p r o c e s s , t h e decision-maker i s b e t t e r p r e p a r e d t o make consistent evaluations a c r o s s alternatives. However, w e cannot e x p e c t and should not r e q u i r e full consistency in any judgmental decision p r o c e s s , s i n c e not all r e l e v a n t a t t r i b u t e s might b e evaluated and t h e r e l e v a n t information on a l t e r n a - tives i s n e v e r completely s h a r e d by all committee members. If e a c h committee member i s asked independently t o specify his o r h e r a s p i r a t i o n and ( o r ) r e s e r v a - tion levels f o r e a c h a t t r i b u t e , a comparison of such r e s u l t s a c r o s s t h e committee and a c r o s s a t t r i b u t e s s e r v e s s e v e r a l purposes:

(a) t h e r e l a t i v e importance of e a c h a t t r i b u t e f o r e a c h committee member and a c r o s s t h e committee, as implied by t h e more o r less attainable levels, becomes ap- p a r e n t , as discussed below.

(b) t h e division of opinions among t h e committee members c a n b e discussed: if a significant s u b s e t of t h e committee h a s high aspirations (reservations) f o r a n at- t r i b u t e and a n o t h e r subset h a s low aspirations (reservations), i t i s a c a s e of a c l e a r disagreement on decision principles. The committee might then discuss t h i s disagreement and come t o a consensus; o r a g r e e t o d i s a g r e e by allowing t h e forma- tion of coalitions t h a t rally f o r t h e importance of various a t t r i b u t e s ( f o r example, when deciding on siting a n industrial facility, a p a r t of t h e t h e committee might b e more concerned with environmental impacts, a n o t h e r more concerned with econom-

(7)

ic impacts).

(c) if t h e discussion shows t h a t t h e r e a s o n f o r disagreement s t e m s from dif- f e r e n t perceptions by various committee members about t h e e x a c t meaning of a p a r t i c u l a r a t t r i b u t e and i t s s c a l e of evaluation, t h e r e s u l t might b e a b e t t e r specification of, o r at l e a s t c o r r e c t i o n s in, t h e list of a t t r i b u t e s .

(d) if t h e committee ( o r a coalition inside t h e committee) a g r e e s t o use a v e r - aged aspiration and ( o r ) r e s e r v a t i o n levels, e a c h committee member has a b e t t e r perception of t h e a n c h o r points t o b e used when evaluating alternatives.

In o r d e r t o s u p p o r t t h e s e discussions, a number of indicators c a n b e comput- ed. Denote t h e individually specified aspiration levels f o r a t t r i b u t e j by t h e com- mittee member k by p ( j , k ) and t h e corresponding r e s e r v a t i o n levels by r ( j , k ).

Then t h e committee "voting" p r o c e d u r e might specify a n averaging of individual in- puts, weighted by t h e voting power coefficients as follows:

Such a n a v e r a g e i s s u b j e c t t o manipulations by committee members who have a n incentive t o d i s t o r t t h e i r t r u e aspirations in o r d e r t o influence t h e e n t i r e com- mittee. A classical remedy, successfully used in subjective evaluations of c e r t a i n s p o r t performances (e.g. ice-skating o r ski-jumping) i s t o exclude outlying opin- ions, in t h i s case deleting t h e highest and t h e lowest p ( j , k ) o r r ( j , k ) a c r o s s a l l k b e f o r e aggregating. This p r o c e d u r a l option motivates committee members t o s t a t e t h e i r p r e f e r e n c e s carefully since they will have n o impact if t h e y voice t h e outly- ing opinions. If t h e committee adopts this option ( o r if i t i s imposed by t h e commit- t e e c h a r t e r ) , t h e n a n aggregation of opinions c a n b e c h a r a c t e r i z e d by:

where

denote t h e committee members with outlying aspiration levels who are t h e r e f o r e excluded from t h e averaging. The calculations a r e similar f o r aggregation of r e s e r v a t i o n levels r ( j ) and k ( r , j ).

2.2. Assessing disagreement

The disagreement about aspiration (reservation) levels f o r a n a t t r i b u t e among t h e committee c a n be measured in various ways. Clustering algorithms c a n b e used in t h e case of v e r y l a r g e numbers of committee members t o identify t h e positional s t r u c t u r e of t h e committee. Or, one could evaluate various statistical moments of t h e distributions of p ( j ,k ) and r ( j ,k ) a c r o s s k , although moments of a distribu- tion do not typically indicate t h e configuration of dissent. A good indicator of disagreement should distinguish between t h e case when t h e r e a r e two o r more siz- a b l e dissenting g r o u p s of committee members, each r e p r e s e n t i n g a uniform opin- ion, and t h e case when t h e differences of opinion a r e distributed uniformly o r at- t r i b u t e d mainly t o outlying opinions. To identify t h e s e differences, a d i s a g r e e - ment i n d i c a t o r c a n b e defined in t h e following way.

(8)

F i r s t l e t us consider t h e absolute change of aspirations:

where committee members are renumbered such t h a t

N o w A P ( j , k ) c a n b e split into t h e distribution of individual changes of opinion:

In t h e s e equations, k c a n b e i n t e r p r e t e d as t h e index of t h e pairwise comparison between t w o r a n k e d committee members. If l a r g e d i f f e r e n c e s o c c u r only at t h e ends of t h e r a n g e of k , corresponding to outlying opinions or small minority groups, t h e y are not as significant as when t h e y o c c u r in t h e middle of t h e r a n g e . To c o r r e c t f o r this, w e introduce a coefficient c (k ):

Other formulae c a n also b e used for t h i s coefficient; t h e a b o v e h a s been selected a f t e r empirical tests. The maximum value of c ( k ) f o r any ( K , k ) i s one.

A l s o , for a l l K , c ( k )

=

0 for both k

=

1 and k =K-1 s i n c e outlying opinions are not counted in t h e aggregation. I t i s useful to define t h e disagreement indicator a s :

This disagreement indicator i s bounded by t h e absolute d i f f e r e n c e of aspirations, A P ( j , k ) ; but D l @ , j) = A P ( j , k ) only if t h e committee i s split into two equal f r a c - tions of equal a s p i r a t i o n s in e a c h fraction. Note t h a t t h e disagreement indicator (5) h a s a peculiar p r o p e r t y : i t i s always equal t o z e r o if K S 3. Clearly t h i s is be- c a u s e a committee of t h r e e always h a s two outlying opinions and only o n e will t h e r e f o r e b e counted in t h e aggregation.

Similarly, disagreement indicators D l ( r , j ) f o r t h e distribution of r e s e r v a t i o n levels A r ( j ,k ) c a n b e computed. If both a s p i r a t i o n and r e s e r v a t i o n levels are used, t h e committee might b e i n t e r e s t e d in disagreement indicators for a v e r a g e s , D I ( p r , j ) , computed for t h e distribution of pr ( j ,k ), defined as:

I t should b e s t r e s s e d t h a t t h e a b o v e indicators s e r v e only t o draw t h e a t t e n - tion of t h e committee to t h e a t t r i b u t e s and a s p i r a t i o n s t h a t c a u s e dissent, f o r which a discussion of d i f f e r e n c e s of opinion might b e useful. Similar disagreement indicators c a n b e used when comparing t h e d i f f e r e n c e s between individual assess- ments of specific a l t e r n a t i v e s .

Another t y p e of indicator relates to t h e r e l a t i v e importance of v a r i o u s a t t r i - b u t e s as implied by specified a s p i r a t i o n s (reservations). Various t y p e s of indica- t o r s can a l s o b e used h e r e . W e choose d o m i n a n t w e i g h t i n g f a c t o r s i m p l i e d by a s p i r a t i o n s as r e l e v a n t indicators because t h e y are consistent with t h e function used later for t h e evaluation of a l t e r n a t i v e s .

To b e consistent with o u r t h e o r e t i c a l decision model, t h e weighting f a c t o r s f o r a t t r i b u t e s are c o n s t r u c t e d as follows: If a committee member specifies a s p i r a t i o n s f o r one a t t r i b u t e t h a t are "closer" to t h e u p p e r end of i t s evaluation scale than a n o t h e r , t h e n t h i s implies t h a t t h i s a t t r i b u t e i s more important to him or h e r than t h e o t h e r . More specifically, a n indicator should b e inversely p r o p o r t i o n a l t o such a distance a n d , if t h e indicators are i n t e r p r e t e d as weighting coefficients, t h e y should b e normalized s o t h a t t h e y sum up t o one across all a t t r i b u t e s . To

(9)

avoid computational e r r o r s , t h e indicators should b e calculable even in such a n unreasonable c a s e t h a t a committee member specifies aspirations equal t o t h e u p p e r end of t h e scale. Hence, w e extend t h e u p p e r bound slightly, denoting i t by u b ( j ) , and f o r simplicity normalize all s c a l e s s o t h a t t h e lower bounds of t h e scales of a l l a t t r i b u t e s are zero. Then t h e dominant weighting f a c t o r s implied by aspiration levels p of a t t r i b u t e s j f o r committee member k are computed as fol- lows:

J

w (P , j

=

( u b ( j ) / ( u b ( j )

-

P ( j .k

I))/

( u b

(?I/

( u b

(7)

- P ( j . k ) ) ) ( 7 ) J = l

Weighting f a c t o r s implied by s t a t e d r e s e r v a t i o n levels w ( r , j ,k ) a r e calculated similarly.

These weighting f a c t o r s can a l s o b e calculated f o r t h e committee's aggregated p r e f e r e n c e s . In a l l c a s e s , t h e indicators s e r v e only as feedback signals t o indivi- duals o r t o t h e committee t o check whether t h e i r a s p i r a t i o n s c o r r e c t l y r e f l e c t t h e i r p e r c e p t i o n of t h e r e l a t i v e importance of various a t t r i b u t e s . If t h e r e a r e in- consistencies, they c a n easily b e c o r r e c t e d .

2.3. E v a l u a t i n g alternatives by individual c o m m i t t e e members

An essential p a r t of t h e decision p r o c e s s i s a n individual assessment and analysis of a l l a l t e r n a t i v e s by e a c h committee member. In t h e a p p r o a c h followed in t h i s p a p e r , i t i s assumed t h a t t h e assessment i s performed not by rankings o r pair- wise comparisons but simply by assigning s c o r e s f o r e a c h a t t r i b u t e t o e a c h alter- native ( a s a t e a c h e r would assign g r a d e s f o r e a c h s u b j e c t of learning t o e a c h pu- pil). Uncertainty in each assessment could b e e x p r e s s e d by supplying a r a n g e of s c o r e s o r a probability distribution f o r t h e s c o r e s ; however, we consider only t h e simpler c a s e without individual assessment of uncertainty. The s c o r e s of t h e k-th committee member f o r t h e j-th a t t r i b u t e of t h e i-th a l t e r n a t i v e a r e denoted h e r e by q ( i . j , k ) .

In o r d e r f o r e a c h committee member t o s e e what t h e s c o r e s imply and check f o r any scoring e r r o r s , rankings of a l t e r n a t i v e s by various a t t r i b u t e s c a n b e pro- duced in t h e system by listing t h e alternatives. s t a r t i n g with t h e b e s t s c o r e on a given a t t r i b u t e and ending with t h e worst s c o r e . However, t h e committee member i s a l s o i n t e r e s t e d in a n a g g r e g a t e ranking which t a k e s into account s c o r e s on a l l at- t r i b u t e s t o test whether his o r h e r intuitive opinion about which a l t e r n a t i v e s are b e s t i s consistent with t h e r e s u l t s of t h e scoring p r o c e d u r e .

A special approximation of a utility function implied by aspiration levels i s ap- plied in o r d e r t o produce such a n a g g r e g a t e ranking; t h i s approximation i s called a n (order-consistent) achievement function.

Consider t h e following question (Wierzbicki, 1986). Suppose t h e u s e r knows t h e u p p e r and lower bounds of a n assessment s c a l e and h a s specified a r e s e r v a t i o n and a n aspiration level f o r e a c h decision a t t r i b u t e ; t h e s e f o u r points w e denote respectively by Lb(j), u b ( j ) , r ( j ) and p ( j ) , where Lb(j)

<

r ( j ) < p ( j )

<

u b ( j ) . Suppose a satisfaction (utility) value of z e r o i s assigned t o a n a l t e r n a t i v e whose at- t r i b u t e assignments are a l l equal t o r e s e r v a t i o n levels, and a satisfaction (utility) value of one t o a n a l t e r n a t i v e whose a t t r i b u t e s a r e a l l equal t o a s p i r a t i o n levels.

We assume f u r t h e r t h a t a l t e r n a t i v e s which have s c o r e s satisfying a l l t h e i r r e s e r - vation levels are p r e f e r r e d t o any a l t e r n a t i v e which h a s at l e a s t one s c o r e not satisfying t h e corresponding r e s e r v a t i o n level. And similarly, a l t e r n a t i v e s which have s c o r e s satisfying all t h e i r aspiration levels a r e p r e f e r r e d t o any a l t e r n a t i v e which h a s at l e a s t one s c o r e not satisfying t h e corresponding aspiration level. Fi- nally, l e t a n (unlikely) a l t e r n a t i v e with s c o r e s all equal t o t h e lower bounds of t h e

(10)

scales have t h e value of d (a negative number) and a n (unlikely) a l t e r n a t i v e with s c o r e s all equal t o t h e u p p e r bounds have t h e value of 1

+

a (a number g r e a t e r than one). What i s t h e simplest cardinal utility function (i.e. a function t h a t i s in- dependent of all l i n e a r transformations of t h e assessment scales) t h a t i s consistent with all of t h e s e assumptions?

The simplest function t h a t meets t h e s e requirements can b e constructed by us- ing l i n e a r approximations between t h e points f o r which i t s values are known ( 4 , 0 , 1 and 1

+

a ) . Such a function, called a l s o a n o r d e r - r e p r e s e n t i n g achievement function, h a s t h e following form:

where

u j ( q ( i , j , k ) , p ( j ) , f ( j ) )

=

and q ( i , k )

=

( q ( i , l , k )

,...,

q ( i . j , k )

,...,

q ( i , J , k ) ) i s t h e v e c t o r of s c o r e s given by t h e k-th committee member t o t h e i-th alternative. Thus t h e achievement function maps a v e c t o r of a t t r i b u t e s into a scalar value f o r e a c h alternative. Additionally, p

=

(P ( I ) ,

. . .

, p ( j ),

. . .

, p ( J ) ) and r = ( r ( I ) ,

. . .

, r ( j ),

. . .

.r ( J ) ) a r e v e c t o r s of a s p i r a t i o n and r e s e r v a t i o n levels aggregated a c r o s s t h e committee in a way t h a t i s a c c e p t - a b l e t o all members. In i t s middle r a n g e , t h e function (8) c a n also b e i n t e r p r e t e d by t h e difference between a s p i r a t i o n and r e s e r v a t i o n levels f o r e a c h a t t r i b u t e .

However, t h e above achievement function h a s some disadvantages. Suppose t h e s c a l e s of assessments f o r all a t t r i b u t e s a r e from 0 t o 1 0 , and t h e r e s e r v a t i o n levels are all 3 while t h e aspiration levels a r e all 7. Compare two alternatives:

one with all s c o r e s equal t o 5 s o t h a t t h e value of t h e achievement function (8) equals 0.5, while t h e second a l t e r n a t i v e h a s s c o r e s of 7 f o r all a t t r i b u t e s but one.

which h a s t h e s c o r e 4 s o t h a t s (q , p , r )

=

0.25. But t h e second a l t e r n a t i v e might b e considered b e t t e r : t h e b e t t e r achievements on many a t t r i b u t e s could compensate f o r a worse achievement on one a t t r i b u t e . In o r d e r t o c o r r e c t f o r t h i s considera- tion, we propose a modified form of t h e function (8), called a n order-approximating achievement function:

J

min u j ( q ( i , j , k ) , p ( j ) , f ( j ) )

+

( E / J ) u j ( q ( i . j . k ) , p ( j ) , f ( j ) ) + E )

=

I1*Y j =l

I

where u j (q ( i , j , k ) , p ( j ) , r ( j ) ) are defined as in (9). The p a r a m e t e r E in t h i s func- tion r e p r e s e n t s t h e intensity of c o r r e c t i o n of t h e worst (under-)achievement by t h e a v e r a g e (over-)achievement. In t h e example considered above, if E

=

1 and t h e r e are 5 a t t r i b u t e s , t h e n t h e f i r s t a l t e r n a t i v e h a s a value of t h e achievement function (10) equal t o 0.5 (due t o t h e subdivision by 1

+

E in ( l o ) , t h i s does not depend on E if all u j are equal) but t h e second a l t e r n a t i v e has t h e corresponding value of 0.55. S o t h e second a l t e r n a t i v e is p r e f e r r e d . If, however, E

=

0.5, then t h e f i r s t a l t e r n a t i v e h a s a n achievement value equal t o 0.5 but t h e second a l t e r n a - tive has a n achievement value of 0.45, s o t h e f i r s t a l t e r n a t i v e i s now p r e f e r r e d .

The choice of t h e p a r a m e t e r E i s l e f t t o t h e committee: if i t s members f e e l t h a t t h e worst achievement matters most, they should choose slight c o r r e c t i o n (say, E

=

0.1); if t h e y f e e l t h a t t h e a v e r a g e achievement m a t t e r s most, they should

(11)

choose v e r y s t r o n g c o r r e c t i o n (say, E

=

2), indicating t h a t a v e r a g e achievement i s twice as important as worst achievement. A good i n t e r p r e t a b i l i t y of t h e values of t h e achievement function (10) by t h e u s e r s is obtained if a =b =1 and t h e values of s ( q ( i , k ) , p , r ) are multiplied by 10. Then t h e achievement r a n g e i s from -10 (corresponding t o a l l s c o r e s equal t o 0) through 0 (all s c o r e s on r e s e r v a t i o n lev- els), through 1 0 (all s c o r e s on aspiration levels) t o 20 (all s c o r e s maximal, equal t o 10).

W e should a l s o mention h e r e some mathematical i n t e r p r e t a t i o n s of t h e dom- inant weighting f a c t o r s implied by aspiration o r r e s e r v a t i o n levels in connection with achievement functions in t h e forms (8) and (10). These achievement functions are nonlinear, hence t h e i r derivatives (corresponding t o t h e classical concept of a weighting f a c t o r in a l i n e a r utility function) depend on q ( i , k ) . In f a c t , t h e s e achievement functions are nondifferentiable, hence they do not possess deriva- tives in t h e classical s e n s e at some points

-

and, in p a r t i c u l a r , at t h e a n c h o r points, t h a t is, if q ( i , k )

=

r o r q ( i , k )

=

p. The dominant weighting f a c t o r s indi- c a t e directions in t h e J-dimensional s p a c e of t h e assessment v e c t o r s q ( i .k ), on which t h e points of nondifferentiability are located. While t h e s e p r o p e r t i e s of t h e dominant weighting f a c t o r s are important mathematically, t h e r e a d e r should remember two points: t h e dominant weighting f a c t o r s are not specified a p r i o r i o r supplied explicitly, r a t h e r they are implied by t h e choice of a s p i r a t i o n and/or of various a t t r i b u t e s as implied by aspiration and/or r e s e r v a t i o n levels.

The achievement function (10) is used t o a g g r e g a t e s c o r e s given by a commit- tee member t o various a t t r i b u t e s of a n a l t e r n a t i v e and then t o r a n k various a l t e r - natives according t o t h e i r achievement values. This c a n b e done when using e i t h e r individual a s p i r a t i o n s (reservations) of a committee member o r aggregated a s p i r a - tions (reservations). In t h e former c a s e , t h e ranking proposed by t h e system s e r v e s as a feedback t o t h e committee member: h e o r s h e should compare i t with his o r h e r intuitive perception of ranking of alternatives. If t h e ranking does not match his o r h e r intuitive perception, he o r s h e should check whether h e did not make any e r r o r s in scoring; a n o t h e r r e a s o n f o r such mismatch might b e his disagreement with t h e c o r r e c t i o n coefficient E adopted by t h e committee. If t h e ranking does match his o r h e r intuitive perception, h e o r s h e should b e p r e p a r e d t o a c c e p t t h e f a c t t h a t t h e ranking based on aggregated aspirations (reservations) might b e different; but t h e committee member cannot p r o t e s t if h e o r s h e a c c e p t s t h e r i g h t of t h e committee t o impose aggregated decision principles on t h e collec- tive group.

2.4. Aggregating individual assessments across the committee

There are various i n t e r p r e t a t i o n s of t h e p r o c e s s of aggregating p r e f e r e n c e s a c r o s s a group of decision-makers. Typically, t h e i n t e r p r e t a t i o n i s r e l a t e d t o t h e concept of fairness; however, various paradoxes in decision t h e o r y (Saari, 1982) show t h a t t h e r e is no absolute meaning in t h i s concept. In this p a p e r , w e simply re- q u i r e t h a t t h e committee specify a set of p r o c e d u r e s t h a t is a c c e p t e d as f a i r by t h e group. For example, if t h e c h a r t e r of t h e committee specifies t h e voting power of e a c h member, t h e procedurally "fair" aggregation is t o t a k e t h e weighted a v e r - a g e of evaluations. The members with g r e a t e r voting power are supposedly e i t h e r more responsible (consider, s a y , t h e r o l e of t h e chairman of t h e committee), more concerned with t h e outcome of t h e decision p r o c e s s , o r more knowledgeable in a c e r t a i n substantive area.

Hence, a final ranking of a l t e r n a t i v e s f o r t h e e n t i r e committee c a n b e pro- posed by t h e decision s u p p o r t system by computing t h e (weighted) a v e r a g e d achievement values f o r e a c h alternative:

(12)

with s ( q ( i , k ) , p , r ) defined a s in (8) or (10).

This aggregation p r o c e d u r e gives r e l i a b l e r e s u l t s under c e r t a i n assumptions, of which t w o are m o s t important. F i r s t , w e assume t h a t committee members d o not bias t h e i r opinions in o r d e r to manipulate t h e outcome of t h e decision p r o c e s s . In o r d e r to discourage such manipulations, it is advisable to exclude outlying opinions f r o m t h e averaging p r o c e s s , as w a s done in (2) f o r t h e aggregation of a s p i r a t i o n levels:

where

& ( i )

=

a r min s ( q ( i , k ) , p , r ) ; c ( i )

=

argmax s ( q ( i , k ) , p , r )

l3rK lee

Second, w e assume t h a t committee members possess t h e same information about a l t e r n a t i v e s . This v e r y demanding assumption is n e v e r fully satisfied in p r a c t i c e . The decision p r o c e s s e n c o u r a g e s discussion and exchange of information a b o u t a l t e r n a t i v e s between committee members in p a r t by including concise descriptions of a l t e r n a t i v e s and r e q u i r i n g agreement a t c e r t a i n s t a g e s . When disagreement is indicated by major d i f f e r e n c e s in individual rankings of a l t e r n a - tives or by l a r g e values of t h e disagreement indicators, t h i s should tell t h e com- mittee to s t o p and s e a r c h for s o u r c e s of disagreement. If t h e disagreement i s d u e to a d i f f e r e n c e in t h e information b a s e between individuals, t h e n t h e problem c a n b e resolved by s h a r i n g and exchanging information. A g r a p h i c r e p r e s e n t a t i o n of t h e diverging scores f o r a n a t t r i b u t e of a n a l t e r n a t i v e helps g r e a t l y in s u c h dis- cussions; a committee member with a dissenting opinion c a n e i t h e r convince t h e committee t h a t h e or s h e h a s specific valuable information to s h a r e , or b e con- vinced t h a t h i s or h e r opinion cannot b e substantiated. This s e r v e s as a n additional disincentive for attempting to manipulate t h e outcome of t h e decision p r o c e s s by biasing assessments. The i n t e r e s t e d r e a d e r should a l s o consult Tversky et a l . (1983) for discussions about b i a s e s in decision-making.

After such discussion, t h e committee c a n e i t h e r decide to r e t u r n t o some ear- l i e r s t a g e of t h e decision p r o c e s s ( f o r example, to correct t h e s c o r e s ) or conclude t h e p r o c e s s . When adopting t h e final decision (a ranking or a selection of a l t e r n a - tives) t h e committee i s by n o means constrained by t h e a g g r e g a t e ranking pro- posed by t h e decision s u p p o r t system, but merely guided by t h e r e s u l t s .

3. PROCEDURAL FRAldEWORK

The a b o v e t h e o r e t i c a l background of a n aspiration-led decision p r o c e s s sug- g e s t s a g e n e r a l p r o c e d u r a l framework for t h e committee; however, t h i s framework i s r a t h e r e l a s t i c a n d c a n b e modified variously for any specific application.

The f i r s t p o i n t on t h e agenda i s to define t h e p r o c e d u r e s by which t h e com- mittee will o p e r a t e . The questions a d d r e s s e d h e r e should include t h e following:

(a) What i s t h e e x p e c t e d p r o d u c t of t h e committee's work and how does i t in- fluence t h e a p p r o p r i a t e p r o c e d u r e ? The answer to t h i s question depends on t h e committee's c h a r t e r and i t s p e r c e i v e d r o l e . For example, if t h e e x p e c t e d p r o d u c t i s a s h o r t list of significantly d i f f e r e n t a l t e r n a t i v e s , p r o c e d u r a l r u l e s will b e dif- f e r e n t f r o m t h e case when t h e e x p e c t e d p r o d u c t i s a consensus opinion on t h e

"best" a l t e r n a t i v e .

(13)

(b) What aggregation r u l e s should b e adopted, and in p a r t i c u l a r , should outly- ing opinions be included in o r excluded from aggregation?

(c) Should t h e committee b e allowed t o divide and form coalitions t h a t might p r e s e n t s e p a r a t e assessments of aspirations, a t t r i b u t e s c o r e s and t h u s final rank- ings of a l t e r n a t i v e s ?

The committee should a l s o become familiar with basic concepts concerning t h e use of t h e decision s u p p o r t system. A s e c r e t a r y o r a designated committee member whose duties include working with t h e decision s u p p o r t system should study thoroughly t h e description of t h e system in t h e u s e r ' s manual (1985), and p r e s e n t t h e basic concepts t o t h e e n t i r e committee in t h e f i r s t meeting.

The s e c o n d p o i n t on t h e agenda i s problem specification. Neither t h e list of a l t e r n a t i v e s , n o r t h e i r descriptions need b e complete a t this stage. The most im- p o r t a n t p a r t of t h i s p r o c e s s t h a t r e q u i r e s discussion and specification by t h e en- t i r e committee is t h e definition of t h e a t t r i b u t e s of t h e decision and t h e i r s c a l e s of assessment.

Various studies in decision t h e o r y suggest t h a t a reasonable number of a t t r i - butes should not e x c e e d seven t o nine ( s e e e.g. Dinkelbach, 1982); if more a t t r i - butes are suggested, t h e y should b e aggregated. For example, t h e r e might b e a l a r g e number of qualitative indicators t h a t are a l l r e l a t e d t o professional r e p u t a - tion; instead of using all t h e s e indicators, i t is b e t t e r t o a s k committee members t o evaluate subjectively t h e a t t r i b u t e "reputation", t h a t i s , t o t r a n s l a t e t h e informa- tion about all t h e s e indicators into one assessment, given originally on a v e r b a l s c a l e from "unacceptable" t o "excellent", into a quantitative s c a l e , say from 0 t o 10.

A c l e a r definition of r e l e v a n t a t t r i b u t e s i s a v e r y important p a r t of t h e deci- sion process. One possible a p p r o a c h is t o f i r s t list a l a r g e number of a t t r i b u t e s , t h e n o r d e r them into groups in a h i e r a r c h i c a l s t r u c t u r e , and finally decide on a s h o r t list of aggregated a t t r i b u t e s satisfying two requirements:

(a) t h e y should h a v e t h e same h i e r a r c h i c a l importance

-

which does not mean t h a t they should b e equally important, b u t they should not obviously d i f f e r in im- p o r t a n c e n o r b e h i e r a r c h i c a l l y dependent;

(b) t h e y should not b e highly c o r r e l a t e d

-

t h a t is, two d i f f e r e n t a t t r i b u t e s should not e x p r e s s , under different names, t h e same essential a s p e c t of t h e deci- sion.

Aggregated a t t r i b u t e s t h a t satisfy t h e s e requirements often h a v e a qualitative c h a r a c t e r . A committee should avoid t h e t r a p of selecting some a t t r i b u t e s only be- cause t h e y might b e quantitatively measurable (such as t h e number of publications of candidates f o r a scientific position). Typically, such a t t r i b u t e s are inadequate and are more r e l e v a n t when e x p r e s s e d in a g g r e g a t e terms.

During t h e t h i r d p o i n t on t h e agenda, aspiration a n d / o r r e s e r v a t i o n levels f o r a l l a t t r i b u t e s a r e determined s e p a r a t e l y by each committee member. After t h e s e values are e n t e r e d into t h e system, all necessary a v e r a g e s and o t h e r indica- t o r s (disagreement indicators, dominant weighting f a c t o r s ) c a n b e computed.

The f o u r t h p o i n t i s t h e analysis and discussion of aspirations by t h e e n t i r e committee. These discussions a r e supported by t h e computed indicators and t h e i r g r a p h i c interpretations.

In t h e s e discussions, t h e committee might a d d r e s s t h e following questions:

(a) Do t h e dominant weighting f a c t o r s a c c u r a t e l y r e f l e c t t h e p e r c e p t i o n s of individual committee members about t h e r e l a t i v e importance of various a t t r i b u t e s (if not, should t h e a s p i r a t i o n s o r r e s e r v a t i o n s b e c o r r e c t e d ) ?

(14)

(b) What a r e t h e r e l e v a n t differences and do they r e p r e s e n t a n essential disagreement about decision principles?

(c) Does t h e e n t i r e committee a g r e e t o use joint, aggregated aspirations (reservations), o r will t h e r e b e s e v e r a l s e p a r a t e sub-group aggregations?

The fiJYh p o i n t on t h e agenda i s a survey of alternatives. Discussions might c e n t e r on t h e following:

(a) Are t h e available descriptions of a l t e r n a t i v e s adequate f o r judging them according t o t h e a c c e p t e d list of a t t r i b u t e s ? If t h e answer i s negative, additional information should b e g a t h e r e d by sending out questionnaires, consulting re- viewers, e t c .

(b) Which of t h e available a l t e r n a t i v e s are i r r e l e v a n t and should b e deleted from t h e list? This kind of c u r s o r y screening c a n b e done in various ways. The com- mittee might define some screening a t t r i b u t e s and r e s e r v a t i o n levels f o r them (of a quantitative o r simple logical s t r u c t u r e ) : f o r example, w e d o not a c c e p t candidates t h a t do not have at least f o u r y e a r s of teaching experience. The s e c r e t a r y c a n b e empowered t o p r e p a r e t h e l i s t of i r r e l e v a n t a l t e r n a t i v e s t o b e deleted; t h i s list should b e presented t o t h e e n t i r e committee f o r approval. I t i s easy t o overlook special opportunities r e l a t e d t o seemingly i r r e l e v a n t a l t e r n a t i v e s .

(c) I s t h e list of relevant a l t e r n a t i v e s promising f o r a reasonable choice? O r should t h e committee look f o r new a l t e r n a t i v e s ? What a r e t h e a t t r i b u t e s t h a t have not been sufficiently w e l l addressed by t h e existing set of a l t e r n a t i v e s ?

Most of t h e s e questions a r e analyzed subjectively without much s u p p o r t from t h e system. However, t h e list of r e l e v a n t a l t e r n a t i v e s must b e sufficiently s h o r t b e f o r e going t o t h e next point on t h e agenda.

Z'he sizth p o i n t on t h e agenda i s t h e individual assessment of alternatives.

The assignment of s c o r e s f o r e a c h a t t r i b u t e t o e a c h a l t e r n a t i v e i s t h e main input of committee members into t h e system. Each member specifies s c o r e s ; t h e system s u p p o r t s this by displaying those assignments a l r e a d y made and t h o s e still t o b e entered.

The s e v e n t h p o i n t on t h e agenda i s individual analysis of a l t e r n a t i v e s , based on calculations of t h e achievement function which lead t o a ranking of all alterna- tives f o r e a c h committee member. This ranking i s t h e main s o u r c e of learning about t h e distribution of a l t e r n a t i v e s r e l a t i v e t o aspirations.

The questions addressed by e a c h member at t h i s point might b e as follows:

(a) Do t h e rankings along e a c h a t t r i b u t e c o r r e c t l y r e p r e s e n t t h e individual's evaluations of a l t e r n a t i v e s ; does t h e achievement ranking, based on individual as- pirations, c o r r e c t l y r e p r e s e n t t h e a g g r e g a t e evaluation (if not, should t h e s c o r e s b e modified)?

(b) If t h e r e remains disagreement about t h e member's individual achievement ranking of a l t e r n a t i v e s suggested by t h e system, should h e o r s h e propose at t h e next committee meeting t o modify t h e p a r a m e t e r E t h a t e x p r e s s e s t h e importance of a v e r a g e achievements as compared t o t h e worst achievement?

(c) If h e o r s h e a g r e e s with t h e individual achievement ranking proposed by t h e system, what are t h e differences between t h i s ranking and t h a t based on indivi- dual s c o r e s but r e l a t e d t o committee-aggregated aspirations? A r e t h e s e differen- c i e s significant, o r c a n h e o r s h e a c c e p t them as t h e r e s u l t of agreement on joint decision principles?

Z'he e i g h t h p o i n t on t h e agenda is a committee discussion of t h e essential differences in scoring and disagreements about t h e preliminary ranking of a l t e r - natives aggregated a c r o s s t h e committee. These discussions a r e s u p p o r t e d by t h e system; t h e system computes indicators of differences of opinion and p r e p a r e s a

(15)

preliminary aggregated ranking.

The questions addressed by t h e committee at this point might b e t h e following:

(a) On which a t t r i b u t e s are t h e l a r g e s t differences in scoring between commit- tee members observed? Do t h e s e differences r e p r e s e n t essential differences in information about t h e same a l t e r n a t i v e ?

(b) What i s t h e essential information ( o r uncertainty about such information) t h a t c a u s e s t h e s e differences? Should additional information b e g a t h e r e d , o r can c e r t a i n committee members supply t h i s information?

(c) Would t h e r e s u l t s of t h e s e discussions and possible changes of scoring in- fluence t h e preliminary aggregated ranking list proposed by t h e system? This c a n b e tested by applying simple sensitivity analyses.

(d) Does t h e preliminary ranking proposed by t h e system c o r r e c t l y r e p r e s e n t prevalent committee p r e f e r e n c e s ? If not, should t h e p a r a m e t e r E b e modified?

A f t e r t h e s e discussions, a r e t u r n to any previous points on t h e agenda i s pos- sible. If t h e committee decides t h a t t h e decision problem h a s been sufficiently clarified, i t can p r o c e e d t o t h e final,

ninth point

on t h e agenda: agreement on t h e aggregated ranking o r selection of one o r more alternatives. I t i s important t o stress again t h a t t h e committee need not stick t o t h e ranking proposed by t h e sys- tem, since t h e p u r p o s e of t h i s ranking

-

as well as of a l l information p r e s e n t e d by t h e system

-

i s t o clarify t h e decision situation r a t h e r t h a n t o p r e s c r i b e t h e action t h a t should b e taken by t h e committee.

4. IMPLEMENTATION ASSUMPTIONS BND EXTENSIONS

A p r o t o t y p e implementation of SCDAS on t h e IBM-PC ( o r compatible computer) i l l u s t r a t e s t h e possibilities of t h e system and s t r e s s e s g r a p h i c presentations t o en- s u r e user-friendliness.

This implementation in BASIC s e r v e s actually only as a n illustration but con- tains a well-documented t u t o r i a l example (of scientific recruitment committee work) and h a s a u s e r ' s manual t h a t allows a n a v e r a g e u s e r t o work with t h e system on his o r h e r own problems. The implementation i s limited in s e v e r a l aspects:

-

only aspiration levels, not aspiration and r e s e r v a t i o n levels, a r e used in t h e de- cision p r o c e s s and in t h e aggregating achievement function;

-

disagreement indicators a r e computed only f o r aspirations, not f o r s c o r e s ;

-

g r a p h i c illustrations, though quite r i c h , d o not y e t completely r e p r e s e n t informa- tion t h a t might b e useful at various s t a g e s of t h e decision process.

This implementation is available from A. Lewandowski at IIASA. Work on t h e next implementation

-

with much more professionally t r e a t e d system details

-

i s in

p r o g r e s s . The new implementation is designed not only to overcome t h e shortcom- ings listed above, but will a l s o a d d r e s s some new issues, such as r e p r e s e n t a t i o n s of uncertainty in scoring, a joint d a t a b a s e of information r e l e v a n t t o t h e decision p r o c e s s and r e s e r v e d fields of t h e d a t a b a s e f o r use by individual members.

REFERENCES

Dinkelbach. W. (1982). Entscheidungsmodelle, Walter d e Gruyter. Berlin, N e w York.

EXPERT CHOICE, Decision S u p p o r t Software Inc., 1983.

(16)

Johnson, S . (1984). Decision s u p p o r t f o r committee selection, I n t e r n a l R e p o r t , International Institute f o r Applied Systems Analysis, Laxenburg, Austria.

Henrion, M. (1981). An Overview of DEMOS. Dept. of Engineering and Dept. of Public Policy. Carnegie-Mellon University, Pittsburgh.

Keeney, R.L. and Raiffa, H. (1976). Decisions with Multiple Objectives: P r e f e r e n c e s and Value Tradeoffs. Wiley, N e w York, 1976.

LIGHTYEAR

-

The Decision S u p p o r t Software, Lightyear, Inc., 1984.

Roy, B. (1971). Problems and methods with multiple objective functions, Math. P r o - gramming, Vol. 1, pp. 233-236.

S a a r i , D. (1982). Inconsistencies of weighted Voting Systems. Math. of Operations Res. Vol. 7.

S a a t y , T.L. (1982). Decision Making f o r Leaders: The Analytical H i e r a r c h y P r o c e s s f o r Decisions in a Complex World, Lifetime Learning Publ., Belmont.

Simon, H. (1958). Administrative Behavior, Mcmillan, New York.

Tversky, A., Kaheman, D. and P . Slovic (1983). Judgement Under Uncertainty:

Heuristic a n d Biases, Cambridge University P r e s s .

Wierzbicki, A.P. (1982). A mathematical basis f o r satisfying decision making, Math.

Modelling, Vol. 3, pp. 391-405.

Wierzbicki, A.P. (1985). Negotiation and mediation in conflicts: p l u r a l rationality and i n t e r a c t i v e decision p r o c e s s e s . In: M. G r a u e r . M. Thompson, A.P.

Wierzbicki, eds: P l u r a l Rationality and I n t e r a c t i v e Decision P r o c e s s e s , Proceedings Sopron, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg, New York, Tokyo.

Wierzbicki, A.P. (1986). On t h e completeness and constructiveness of p a r a m e t r i c c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n s t o v e c t o r optimization problems. To a p p e a r in OR-Spektrum.

Referenzen

ÄHNLICHE DOKUMENTE

c) if the aspiration levels, either by chance or as a result of interactive learning by the user, are just attainable and correspond t o efficient outcomes,

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLIED SYSTEMS ANALYSIS A-2361 Laxenburg,

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLIED SYSTEMS ANALYSIS A-2361

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLIED SYSTEMS ANALYSIS 2361 Laxenburg,

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLIED SYSTEMS ANALYSIS 2361 Laxenburg, Austria... Antonovsky and

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLIED SYSTEMS ANALYSIS 2361 Laxenburg, Austria.. Kurzhanski Chairman System and Decision Sciences Program.. Nonlinear programming stability

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLIED SYSTEMS ANALYSIS 2361 Laxenburg, Austria... DECISION SUPPORT SYSTEX

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLIED SYSTEMS ANALYSIS A-2361 Laxenburg,