• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

Religion in Philosophy and Theology

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Aktie "Religion in Philosophy and Theology"

Copied!
29
0
0

Wird geladen.... (Jetzt Volltext ansehen)

Volltext

(1)
(2)

Religion in Philosophy and Theology

Editor

Ingolf U. Dalferth (Claremont)

Advisory Board

Jean-Luc Marion (Paris/Chicago) Thomas Rentsch (Dresden) Heiko Schulz (Frankfurt a. M.)

Eleonore Stump (St. Louis)

99

(3)
(4)

Matthew Ryan Robinson

Redeeming Relationship, Relationships that Redeem

Free Sociability and the Completion of Humanity in the Thought of Friedrich Schleiermacher

Mohr Siebeck

(5)

Matthew Ryan Robinson, born 1982; 2009 MDiv from the University of Chicago Divinity School; 2015 PhD from Northwestern University in Religious Studies; currently Research As- sistant in Practical Theology in the Protestant Theological Faculty of the Rheinische Friedrich- Wilhelms-University Bonn.

ISBN 978-3-16-155587-9 / eISBN 978-3-16-155588-6 DOI 10.1628 / 978-3-16-155588-6

ISSN 1616-346X / eISSN 2568-7425 (Religion in Philosophy and Theology)

The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliographie;

detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de.

© 2018 Mohr Siebeck Tübingen. www.mohrsiebeck.com

This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This applies particularly to repro- ductions, translations and storage and processing in electronic systems.

The book was typeset by epline in Böblingen using Times New Roman typeface, printed on non-aging paper by Laupp & Göbel in Gomaringen, and bound by Buchbinderei Nädele in Nehren.

Printed in Germany.

(6)

From and for Christine, Wesley, and Zola

(7)
(8)

Foreword

This book on the ways personal relationships form individuals’ senses and tastes of ultimate reality is itself the product of many relationships, of which I can highlight only a few. In my immediate, institutional circle, I am deeply grateful to my doctoral advisor, Christine Helmer, for challenging me to view the relationship between theol- ogy and religious studies as mutually enriching. I also want to thank Cristina Traina, a model friend, colleague, and mentor; I am deeply grateful to her for her extensive, detailed, and insightful feedback. And I thank the Theology Colloquium at North- western University – Stephanie, Benjamin, Aaron, Teddy, Candace, and Joel – for the opportunity to present drafts of portions of the book and for their truly excellent reading and feedback. All of these folks exhibit a kind of concern for and interest in the work of others that I sincerely hope I emulate in my own collegial relationships.

Over the years, I have been deeply grateful for relationships formed through trav- el and professional networks, of which, again, I can only single out but a handful:

It was Kevin Hector who first introduced me to Schleiermacher and supervised my M. Div thesis on the latter; his influence is still detectable in chapter seven. Wilhelm Gräb was my host as a DAAD research scholar at Humboldt University (Berlin) and has become a valued friend and intellectual influence; when I think of the personal friendliness, scholarly production, and pastoral concern of Schleiermacher, I usually think of Wilhelm. And I thank the DAAD for funding my stay in Berlin 2012–2013 for initial research on this project.

Andreas Arndt, Sarah Schmidt, and Simon Gerber, editors of the Schleiermacher KGA at the Berlin-Brandenburgische Akademie der Wissenschaften, were consis- tently generous in conversation, classes, and conferences at several points along the way. My reading of Schleiermacher is certainly marked by their interpretations. Diet- rich Korsch generously offered to devote a small weekend seminar in Austria to the Monologen; my reading of this text was born in that intimate setting. Our periodic engagements over the past several years have always prompted fresh theological in- sights.

I owe sincere thanks to the Schleiermacher Gesellschaft for its generous support, for the opportunity to present my work in progress over the years, and for the always detailed and precise feedback from the expert readers of Schleiermacher who attend its annual colloquium. The Schleiermacher group of the AAR provided a valuable opportunity to present an early chapter draft.

I thank the Columbia Council for European Studies for funding my pre-disser- tation research that helped me initially to identify the constellation of concepts and questions here developed as a potential dissertation project.

(9)

VIII Foreword

Jesper Svartnik and the Swedish Theological Institute in Jerusalem offered hos- pitality and space to write and reflect as I worked on my first draft of the whole work;

Jesper´s warm invitation to attend an interfaith theology conference in Jerusalem has proved a turning point for me in my thinking on a theology of friendship, which I hope will grow out of the present study.

Finally, friends provide just vital forms of insight, critique, and encouragement, and their presences fill the dissertation. Kyle was my “spiritual director” for things academic and non- at crucial moments. Time spent with my dear friend Jonas always presents the most stimulating conversations on religion, Schleiermacher, Romanti- cism, music and arts, and European history, politics, and culture more broadly. With- out Joel and Candace, finishing this work would have been impossible. And Andrew, well, you’re the muse of redemptive friendship.

My sincere thanks go to the editors at Mohr Siebeck, Henning Ziebritzki and Klaus Hermannstädter. And special thanks are due to Maria Rothmund for her careful copy-editing. This book is a revision of my dissertation thesis, written at Northwest- ern University in the Department of Religious Studies. Revised parts of chapter four first appeared in Der Mensch und seine Seele (de Gruyter, 2017).1

Bonn, June 2017 Matthew Ryan Robinson

1 Matthew Ryan Robinson, “Vollendet: The Completion of Humanity, the Gospel of John, and the Intersubjective Soul of Schleiermacher’s Monologen,” pages 405–420 in Arnulf Scheliha / Jörg Dierken, ed., Der Mensch und seine Seele. Bildung – Frömmigkeit – Ästhetik. Akten des Internationa­

len Kongresses der Schleiermacher­Gesellschaft in Münster, September 2015, Schleiermacher-Ar- chiv 26 (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2017).

(10)

Contents

Chapter 1: Introduction: Religion, Relationships, and

the Completion of Humanity . . . 1 1.1 Religion, Sociability, and the Completion of Humanity . . . 1 1.2 The Relational Religious Subject: The Completion of Humanity

and the Contemporary Study of Religion . . . 4 1.3 Religion’s “More” as a Space of Intersubjectivity . . . 6 1.4 Schleiermacher on Religion: Human Sociability Aimed at Completion . . . 8 1.5 Project Overview: Sociability in Schleiermacher, Sociability and

Religious Formation, Sociability as Intentional Practice . . . 10 Chapter 2: Sociability: A Historical Contextualization . . . 13 2.1 Introduction . . . 13 2.2 Roots of Geselligkeit in the German Enlightenment, Pietism, and

Popular Literature of the Eighteenth Century . . . 13 2.3 Schiller’s Briefe on the “Perfect Reciprocity” (vollkommene Wechselwirkung)

that “completes the idea of humanity” (den Begriff der Menschheit vollendet) 24 2.4 The Context of Geselligkeit in the Early Romantic Movement of 1790s Berlin 27 2.5 Conclusion . . . 32 Chapter 3: Sociable Humanity: Origins and Aims of an

Intersubjective Anthropology . . . 35 3.1 Introduction . . . 35 3.2 The Sociable Life of Schleiermacher . . . 35 3.3 Toward Free Sociability as an Anthropological Concept: Notes on Aristotle

and “On the Highest Good” . . . 41 3.4 Conclusion: Schleiermacher’s Sociable Anthropology . . . 49 Chapter 4: Free Sociability: Representing Human Action Aimed

at Completion . . . 51 4.1 Introduction . . . 51 4.2 State of the Question: Research on Schleiermacher’s Theory

of Free Sociability . . . 52 4.3 Toward a Complete Vision of Humanity . . . 58 4.4 Empirically and Speculatively “Natural”: Schleiermacher’s Critique of

Adolph Freiherr Knigge . . . 59

(11)

X Contents

4.5 The Completion of Human Perfection as the telos of Free Sociability . . . 62

4.6 The Derivation of the Principle of Reciprocity (Wechselwirkung) from the telos of Free Sociability . . . 64

4.7 The Quantitative Law of Formal and Material Sociability . . . 69

4.8 Conclusion: Is the Versuch a Fragment? The Integrity of the Quantitative Law as a Theory of Human Sociability in Outline . . . 72

Chapter 5: The Sociable Society: The Completion of Humanity through Reciprocal Community with the Whole . . . 75

5.1 Introduction . . . 75

5.2 Schleiermacher’s Versuch and Brouillon in Comparison: A Series of Interesting Parallels . . . 79

5.3 The Completion of Humanity as Subject and Object of the Brouillon . . . 85

5.4 Placing Free Sociability in Schleiermacher’s Ethics . . . 93

5.5 Free Sociability in All Spheres of Life . . . 98

5.6 Conclusion . . . 102

Chapter 6: Sociable Religion:The Finitude of Human Life before the Infinite . . . 105

6.1 Introduction: Personal Relationships and Religious Formation . . . 105

6.2 “Humanity” and “Completion” in On Religion (1799) . . . 109

6.3 “Humanity” and “Completion” in the Soliloquies (1800) . . . 118

6.4 Conclusion: Looking Ahead, Looking Back . . . 138

Chapter 7: Sociability as Theological Practice: Free Sociability in Schleiermacher’s Soteriology and Ecclesiology . . . 141

7.1 Introduction . . . 141

7.2 Christmas Eve’s (1806) Theology of Redemption . . . 144

7.3 The Christian Faith’s Theology of Redemption and its Mediation . . . 154

7.4 The Office of the Keys as Doctrinal and Social Form of the Operation of the Spirit of Christ in Schleiermacher . . . 160

7.5 Conclusion . . . 166

Chapter 8: Conclusion: Relationships that Redeem? Religion in Critical Relationship . . . 169

8.1 Introduction . . . 169

8.2 John Howard Yoder: The Infinite Deferral rather than Infinite Approach to Reconciliation . . . 170

8.3 Dietrich Bonhoeffer and Jennifer McBride: A Theology of Non-Triumphal Repentance and For-Givenness . . . 173

8.4 Conclusion . . . 177

(12)

Contents XI

Bibliography . . . 181

Primary Sources by Schleiermacher . . . 181

Available English Translations of Primary Sources . . . 182

Secondary Literature . . . 183

Index of Subjects . . . 195

Index of Names . . . 199

(13)
(14)

Chapter 1

Introduction:

Religion, Relationships, and the Completion of Humanity

1.1 Religion, Sociability, and the Completion of Humanity In his Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle maintained that “a human being is by nature a socio-political (Greek, politikon) being.” He used this dictum in two places in that work. In the first book, it occurs in the context of a broad examination of the nature of the good in relation to happiness. Aristotle argues that the human is most happy, not with one among many goods, potentially chosen for a variety of reasons, but with that which is chosen for its own sake, and that which is chosen for its own sake is complete without qualification. It is in this connection that Aristotle further claims that this complete good “is thought to be self-sufficient.”1 The human being is not self-sufficient on its own but rather approaches the completion of the good as a part of a vast network of relationships embracing the whole of the social.

In the ninth book of the Nicomachean Ethics, however, when Aristotle repeats the mantra, the context is different, or more specifically, narrower. At a fundamen- tal level, of course, the guiding question still concerns the nature and practice of the good. But now Aristotle is discussing the role of friendship in particular. The con- nection to the question of “completion” remains, but it is focused on the relation to the friend. “A friend, since he is another self, provides what a person cannot provide by himself,”2 and this not only in a material way but through a relationship of mutual self-formation of character and virtue. So he says again, “a human is a socio-political being and his nature is to live in the company of others.”3 Importantly, here the ques- tion of the role of relationships in pursuit of the good is not merely a matter of an in- dividual person’s being part of a society but is more specifically a matter of person- al relationships. “So this will be the case with the happy person as well, because he possesses the natural goods, and it is clearly better to spend his days with friends and good people than with strangers or anybody he happens to bump into. So the happy person does need friends.”4 Friendship, a personal relationship of virtue with partic- ular others, is seen as inseparable from the pursuit of human completion entailed in what Aristotle calls the good.

But what is the relationship between these “two levels,” so-to-speak, of human relationality – namely, between the relationality of the individual to its “completion”

1 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. and ed. Roger Crisp, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 11.

2 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 177.

3 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 177.

4 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 177.

(15)

2 Chapter 1: Introduction

and the relationality of individuals with one another? How are the personal relation- ships of the latter influenced and determined by understandings of the former and vice versa?

These are questions Friedrich Schleiermacher (1768–1834) began working through at an early age and which eventually became determinative for the construc- tion of his ethical and theological thought. The earliest extant writings by Schleier- macher, aside from personal correspondence, are notes and translations he made in 1788–89 of books eight and nine of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. In this work one finds him reflecting on the conditions of happiness and individual development, like Aristotle, in relation to friendship.5 In this work, Schleiermacher reflects on the con- cept of Geselligkeit, or “sociability,” as an unavoidable tendency based in human ex- perience and as a form of action that orients persons in understandings and practices of completing the human good. The interrelations of these two concepts – sociabil- ity and the completion of humanity – form the central focus of the following study.

Aristotle had posed the question of the value of beneficence in book eight.

Schleiermacher interprets the question as an inquiry concerning the possibilities for satisfying “deficiencies of the human condition,” and he argues that the Geselligkeit of friendship is uniquely capable of filling up what the individual lacks. Indeed, he places the emphasis not on friendship per se but on the sociable content of friend- ship: Sociability is a reciprocal sharing of thoughts and feelings among equals “for their optimal benefit.” Picking up on an aesthetic tradition inaugurated by Baum- garten and developed further in Kant’s critique of judgment and Schiller’s letters on the aesthetic education of humanity, Schleiermacher writes that the “play” (Spiel) of sociability gives one new perspectives on oneself and yields, for the individuals in- volved, corporately, experiences that are “completely new” for all of them.6

In this way, sociability in the relationship with a friend forms the foundation of human freedom, as Schleiermacher understood the idea. Schleiermacher already in- timates this more fundamental and comprehensive ethical view of the potential of sociability in his notes on Aristotle when he writes that people “soon long for con- nection with like-minded beings, in order through their shared powers to open a wider field for moral action, and in order better to confront the hindrances inevitably encountered on the road of moral activity.”7 In another early essay, written roughly contemporaneously with the notes on Aristotle, Schleiermacher illustrates this point by referring to the jump from individual hunting to shared agricultural labor.8 This

5 Friedrich Schleiermacher, “Anmerkungen zu Aristoteles: Nikomachische Ethik 8–9 (1788),”

pages 1–44 in Günter Mecken stock, ed., Jugendschriften 1787–1796, Volume I / 1 of Kritische Ge- samtausgabe (KGA) (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2011). English translation of pages 3–7 of the Anmerkungen as found in the KGA: Friedrich Schleiermacher, “Notes on Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics 8–9,”

trans. John Hoffmeyer, Theology Today 56, no. 2 (1999): 164–168.

6 Schleiermacher, “Anmerkungen zu Aristoteles,” KGA I/1, 5 = “Notes on Aristotle,” 167. Com- pare also Alexander Gott lieb Baumgarten, Ästhetik. Teil 1: §§ 1–613, trans. and ed. by Dagmar Mir- bach (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2007).

7 Schleiermacher, “Anmerkungen zu Aristoteles,” KGA I/1, 6 = “Notes on Aristotle,” 168.

8 Friedrich Schleiermacher, “Über das höchste Gut (1789),” pages 83–125 in Günter Mecken- stock, ed., Jugendschriften 1787–1796, KGA I/1 (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2011). H. Victor Froese has produced an English Translation: Friedrich Schleiermacher, On the Highest Good, trans. and with a

(16)

1.1 Religion, Sociability, and the Completion of Humanity 3 reflects the way that sociability for Schleiermacher just is a communal pursuit of the realization and completion of human freedom in nature as part of nature, on the in- dividual and species-universal level: In sociability, individuals and groups identi- fy needs, desires, and incapacities for satisfying them; in sociability, they develop strategies and resources for satisfying those needs and desires; and through socia- bility they construct visions of what a full realization of the potential for freedom in nature might mean and look like. Thus is sociability inherently a pursuit of the re- alization of human freedom in nature. When one allows the ideas of others to “mix with one’s own,”9 new vistas of individual and communal possibility open, and the future approaches the present.

Schleiermacher’s notes on Aristotle thus hint at a fundamental importance of so- ciability for the complete realization of what it means to be a human being, individ- ually, socially, and civilizationally. In the chapters that follow, I explore the concept of sociability in Schleiermacher’s thought. In particular, I examine the conjunction of sociability with the idea of “the completion of humanity” and the potential signif- icance of this conjunction for understanding the role of close personal relationships in religious formation. This entails consideration of three questions. First, how is sociability to be placed in Schleiermacher, both contextually in his intellectual en- vironment and systematically in his own thought? Answering this question will in- clude a reconstruction of the relevant development of the concept of Geselligkeit and Schleiermacher’s reception of that concept and analysis of the way Schleiermacher used his own theorization of Geselligkeit to organize his ethics, which provide his comprehensive account of the completion of humanity. Second, Schleiermacher also understood sociability to be vitally important for religion and vice-versa, declaring in his fourth speech on religion that religion is “the most complete result of human sociability.”10 Thus the second question is, what is the relationship between socia- bility and religion generally, and, more specifically, how do close personal relation- ships facilitate religious formation in individuals and communities? Answering this question in Schleiermacher will require an integrated theoretical analysis, on the one hand, of religious experience and individual religious development with, on the other hand, the ethical terminology of intersubjectivity such as physical need, equality, mu- tuality, voluntarity, and freedom of expression. Third, because my project, rooted in the theories and methodologies of religious studies, is nevertheless also a project in theology, I want to ask, what happens when religious persons become self-aware of and intentional about making a sociable approach to religion? What kind of doctrine does sociability yield, what are its vulnerabilities for the human persons involved, and what resources does it offer for protections against those vulnerabilities?

scholarly postscript by H. Victor Froese, Schleiermacher Studies and Translations 10 (Lewiston, NY:

Edwin Mellen Press, 1992).

9 Schleiermacher, “Anmerkungen zu Aristoteles,” KGA I/1, 5 = “Notes on Aristotle,” 167.

10 Friedrich Schleiermacher, “Über die Religion. Reden an die Gebildeten unter ihren Veräch- tern (1799),” pages 185–326 in Günter Mecken stock, ed., Schriften aus der Berliner Zeit 1796–1799, KGA I/2 (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2011), 270; Friedrich Schleiermacher, On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured Despisers, ed. and trans. by Richard Crouter, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 75.

(17)

4 Chapter 1: Introduction

1.2 The Relational Religious Subject: The Completion of Humanity and the Contemporary Study of Religion

The disciplines of religious studies and theology, I believe, stand to benefit from a deepened understanding of the dynamic role sociability plays in the production and governance of religious and theological ideals. Schleiermacher was a founding an- cestor for both disciplines in their modern forms, and thinking about sociability and completion with Schleiermacher sheds insight into religious aspects of sociability and the relational nature of theological notions of the human.

Scholarly study of religion over the past few decades has placed a strong empha- sis on the role of objects and bodies in religion. This has brought about a correspond- ing emphasis on modes of relation that characterize the conjunction of objects and bodies, in particular, discipline, ritual, practice, and discourse. The methodological approaches deemed most effective for understanding that these kinds of relations have often been genealogical and historicist. Such methods have drawn our attention to the pervasiveness of powers and social construction in governing religious be- longing by asking what authorities produce and regulate religious subjects and what historical conditions explain the appearance both of the authorities and of subjects.

I affirm, with scholars like Robert A. Orsi and those working in conversation with Orsi, like Constance M. Furey, and Brenna Moore, that these have been positive de- velopments. Furey notes that these developments have pushed the study of religion past “the Protestant-style tendency to equate religion with interiority and belief,”11 and Moore makes it a priority in her writing that “emphases on the power a society exerts would not go by the wayside.”12

Still, as Furey writes, “attention to practice, performance, authorizing discourse, and subjectifying power has focused attention on the subject in relation to society but not on the relational subject, formed and enacted through sustained affiliations and intense encounters.”13 In the face of long traditions of discipline and comprehensive social institutions of authorizing discourse – both so impersonal in nature – the idea that one’s intimate personal relationships might play a significant role in the for- mation of the religious subject seems old-fashioned and possibly even a bit naïve.

Both Furey and Moore identify the “occlusion” and “loss” of the individual in this move, referring to Robert Orsi’s analysis of what has happened in the study of relig- ious subjects. Moore points to Orsi’s diagnosis that “by ignoring the web of relation- ships in which the subject comes to be and always exists, the individual as a living multi-dimensional reality disappears as well into the mass … the individual becomes a cypher of discourse, discipline, and power in much writing on religion.”14 Furey

11 Constance Furey analyzes these developments in the study of religion along with its con- sequences in “Body, Society, and Subjectivity in Religious Studies,” Journal of the American Acade- my of Religion 80, no. 1 (2012): 7–33 (here page 9).

12 Brenna Moore, “Friendship and the Cultivation of Religious Sensibilities,” Journal of the American Academy of Religion 83, no. 2 (2015): 437–463 (here page 444; emphasis in original).

13 Furey, “Body, Society, and Subjectivity in Religious Studies,” 9.

14 Moore, “Friendship and the Cultivation of Religious Sensibilities,” 439; quoting Robert A. Orsi, “What are our Academic Assumptions about Religion?” pages 9–10 in Philipp Goff and

(18)

1.2 The Relational Religious Subject 5 accordingly echoes Orsi’s summons “to study not just ‘sacred rituals, practices, sym- bols, prayers, and faith of the people,’ but also ‘the totality of their ultimate values, their most deeply held ethical convictions, their efforts to order their reality, their cosmology.’”15

So a new conversation is emerging in contemporary religious studies, giving new attention to the interrelation of close personal relationships and human beings’ ef- forts to construct and organize completed relationships to reality. Orsi, Furey, Moore, and a few others are synthesizing theories and methods drawn from studies in relat- ed fields such as cultural studies, political theory, cultural anthropology, and critical theory to forge a new path in religious studies that “brings relationality back into play” and indeed thinks of “religion as relationship.”16

Moore’s recent article in the Journal of the American Academy of Religion devel- ops this impulse in an insightful way that traces the interdependence of “religious sensibilities” and intimate personal bonds in her research on the French Catholic re- vival of the early twentieth-century. Moore’s basic claim is that the “religious sensi- bilities” of many of the individuals she studies formed through shared experiences of life in community with close friends. She supports this thesis with an examination of personal correspondence documenting the religious development of Jacques and Raïssa Maritain and friends. They refer to the “experience of God” in the voice of a friend, the ways that the ordinariness of life became “more real” through shared com- pany, realizations of “joy” and “love” with one another generating “a real inner expe- rience,” and so on. Poignantly getting at the content and mechanics of the ways these relationships were instrumental for religious experience, Moore relates Jacque Mar- itain’s reception of letters from a friend as “graces from God” and his reply in which he writes “you are Friendship itself, you are Love itself.” The point, for Moore, is that these experiences “were made possible only through sustained, relational en- counters,” that these relationships did not simply teach one another “‘about’ God, but that their relationship creates experiences of God.” “Whether it was ‘finding faith,’

‘knowing a spiritual experience,’ or endowing life with a new ‘richness’ and ‘glory,’

these kinds of experiences were made possible in and through close, personal ex- changes.”17 These examples illustrate the significance of relationships for developing the “religious sensibilities” and forming “the religious sensorium.”

The special challenge is to explain both theoretically and practically what those terms mean18 and how close relationships with others do this. What is specifically re- Rebecca Vasko, eds., Proceedings: Second Biennial Conference on Religion and American Culture (Indianapolis: Indiana University – Purdue University, 2011), 9.

15 Furey, “Body, Society, and Subjectivity in Religious Studies,” 15; quoting Robert A. Orsi, The Madonna of 115th Street: Faith and Community in Italian Harlem, 1880–1950 (New Haven, CT:

Yale University Press, 2010), xvii.

16 Furey, “Body, Society, and Subjectivity in Religious Studies,” 10; here Furey is referring to Orsi’s proposed paradigm shift in Robert A. Orsi, Between Heaven and Earth: The Religious Worlds People Make and the Scholars Who Study Them (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005), e. g. 2–6.

17 Moore, “Friendship and the Cultivation of Religious Sensibilities,” 450.

18 Moore, “Friendship and the Cultivation of Religious Sensibilities,” 440, n. 3 mentions she is following Talal Asad’s understanding of “sensibilities” from Talal Asad, “Thinking about Religion,

(19)

6 Chapter 1: Introduction

ligious about this interiority and the exterior intersubjectivity that forms it? What can be said about the essentially relational and interpersonal quality of religion through a thick description of the contents of those intimate bonds (in relation, e. g., to pain, need, pleasure and freedom), the subjects they lift up (i. e., persons determined by their empirically given circumstances), and their transformative power (to liberate persons for the pursuit of individual and shared flourishing in their organizations of reality)? Moore’s intervention introduces these ideas and invites others to continue the project outlined by Orsi. In particular, we might radicalize the insight of Orsi’s approach to “religion as relationship”19 – in the mathematical sense of following it all the way down to the “roots” – by examining the ways that human relationships, and in particular the sociability that animates those relationships, constitute religion.

In this way, too, we can gain a clearer view of what at first appeared to be – and may or may not actually be – “off from the everyday.”

1.3 Religion’s “More” as a Space of Intersubjectivity

Orsi has invited scholars of religion to re-examine the reality of this “off from the ev- eryday,” or what he has also described as “the more” in religion.20 In his essay “The Problem of the Holy,” Orsi presents the long-existent tension in religious studies between, on the one hand, “modern ways of thinking” in which “there is no ‘out of’

history and culture, no place antecedent to or outside of” one’s socio-historical situ- atedness and, on the other hand, the “experience of the holy, the really real, or the 2 + 2 = 5.”21 All too often, scientific respectability has required strict adherence to the former position, leaving the latter – pejoratively – stuff for “believers.” The religious subject and his or her experience, actions and relations, then, have little to contrib- ute to scholarly understandings; the religious person is rendered sufficiently legible through her or his emplotment in a framework of textual, ritual, and disciplinary tra- ditions. But in consequence, the empirical individual – the one actually acting with intention, out of physical necessity, existential freedom, moved by desire, and in- spired by hope – vanishes, and with her or him, a large quantity of the empirical sub- ject matter of religious studies.22 More importantly, “the more” and “really real” of the individual’s religious experience is, with this move, permanently defined as un- definable and, therefore, as inadmissible in scientific inquiry. Orsi thus shows that the

“scientific” restriction of analyzable religious content to social forces – a restriction ostensibly based on a commitment to the limits of history and culture – yields a self- fulfilling prophecy.

Belief, and Politics,” pages 36–57 in Robert A. Orsi, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Religious Studies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011).

19 Orsi, Between Heaven and Earth, 3.

20 Robert A. Orsi, “The Problem of the Holy,” pages 84–106 in Robert A. Orsi, ed., The Cam- bridge Companion to Religious Studies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 101.

21 Orsi, “The Problem of the Holy,” 97, 104.

22 Orsi, Between Heaven and Earth, 6.

(20)

1.3 Religion’s “More” as a Space of Intersubjectivity 7 So what does Orsi mean in using terminology like “the really real” and “the more”? Is he calling scholars of religion to newly theorize, even themselves expe- rience, something wholly Other from history and culture? The place to look for an answer to these questions is an “in-between” kind of space that Orsi has advocated across his work, from Thank You, St. Jude23 to Between Heaven and Earth to his no- tion of “Abundant History.”24 And this in-between space is precisely a space of per- sonal relationships with others – family, friends, mentors and other guides, living and dead.25 He concludes “The Problem of the Holy” by saying, “The experience of the holy blurs certain boundaries of the real … between here and there, for instance, the past and the present, or between one person and another.”26 Tyler Roberts has begun to develop the implications of Orsi’s orientation to this in-between space by drawing attention to the inter-subjective contents of this space of “the more” where individ- uals encounter the “really real.”

Roberts begins with a basic critique of historicism, distinguishing between meth- odological and metaphysical historicism. The latter violates the historicist impulse by ontologizing historicism, but the former is ultimately unable to account for its presuppositions about reality. Roberts concludes that – whatever else we might think is real on historicist-empiricist grounds – we must accept the reality of this “impos- sible” situation, “ontologizing, that is, our inability to ontologize.”27 Human reality, whatever else may be true of it, is at least also a condition of being unable to give a final account of the really real. Wanting to be clear that he intends more than a re- statement of a tired skepticism, Roberts then builds out this ontological “reality”

positively as a space of active, abiding difference. He argues “the Real” space of the limits of finite knowing is a space of “multiple perspectival inconsistencies between phenomena” and “the gap between different ‘finite determinations.’”28

Orsi and Roberts outline the “really real” in a way that allows us now to see and draw out its intersubjective character. What is really real is that human persons find themselves drawn up short in their ability to account for the totality of reality and their place in it. They also find themselves inextricably woven into intersubjective re- lationships of interdependence; these relationships discretely fill-up certain individ- ual incompletenesses but only by expanding persons’ awareness of the vastness of reality, and thereby intensifying and deepening the overall sense of incompleteness.

What is real is a sense of individual and corporate incompleteness, intersubjectively rendered, and existing before the vastness of all things.29

23 Robert A. Orsi, Thank You, St. Jude: Women’s Devotion to the Patron Saint of Hopeless Causes (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996).

24 Robert A. Orsi, “Abundant History: Marian Apparitions as Alternative Modernity,” Histori- cally Speaking 9, no. 7 (2008): 12–16.

25 Cf. Orsi, Between Heaven and Earth, especially page 13 and following where he discusses in an intentionally self-reflective way the role of such relationships in his own life and work as a scholar.

26 Orsi, “The Problem of the Holy,” 104.

27 Tyler Roberts, “Between the Lines: Exceeding Historicism in the Study of Religion,” Journal of the American Academy of Religion 74, no. 3 (2006): 697–719 (here page 705).

28 Roberts, “Between the Lines,” 706.

29 I use the terminology of “vastness” throughout the present work. Although I am not following or engaging Michael Fishbane directly in this project, I owe my reception of “vastness” to him. His sense for and articulation of the vastness of all things in seminars and in his book Sacred Attunement

(21)

8 Chapter 1: Introduction

The “really real” here (and I am layering Orsi’s terminology onto Roberts) is not simply missing information between the gaps. It is, rather, experienced as “a sign that reality itself is ‘incomplete,’ open, an actualization of the underlying virtual process of becoming.”30 In spaces in-between phenomena – in-between subjects and objects and, especially between subjects and subjects – a process of living, exploring, and forming identities through exchange, comparison, and evaluation of difference takes place. Symbols, traditions, and institutions quickly begin to take shape to help sta- bilize those identities, but we should guard against viewing such stabilizers as the form of the real itself. Too often, they smooth the wrinkles, cover the gaps, deny dif- ference.

But a different objective presents itself: namely, to incorporate and continuously synthesize the realities of one’s incomplete, diverse, and intersubjective embedded- ness in the vastness of all things into one’s self-relation. A structure of active dynam- ics of interaction among incomplete subjects forms the base, while the seeming inex- haustibility of the vastness of reality forms the ceiling. This event-like structure, as a structure of ever-becoming, is always a structure of something different and other, something new, “something more” than one is31 – indeterminable, unpredictable, but ever presenting new possibilities for relating to oneself and others in healthy, life-promoting ways. This “real more” is not merely “external” to subjects but is an aspect of the reality of individual and corporate subjectivity itself. The process of be- coming oneself is a process of developing a self-relation that is harmonious with the totality of things through dynamic exchange and collaboration with others different than oneself, all of whom are involved in the same process.

In short, we might approach the nature of religion’s “really real,” the “more,” and even “the holy” as a fundamental human striving for a completed and perfected self- relation, individually and universally, in the face of the vastness of all things, and see this self-relation as rooted in the rich, if fragile environment of personal relationships and sociability. By viewing the “excessive” in human experience through the concep- tuality of sociability, we discover an inherently religious quality in interpersonal re- lationships and, simultaneously, recover for the study of religion the uniqueness and dignity of every individual’s experience.

1.4 Schleiermacher on Religion:

Human Sociability Aimed at Completion

Friedrich Schleiermacher’s notion of sociability, Geselligkeit, most clearly and con- sequentially articulated in the period up through his first lectures on ethics and the writing of his Christmas Eve dialogue, proves a helpful resource for a radical analy- have made a lasting impression on me. See Michael Fishbane, Sacred Attunement: A Jewish Theolo- gy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008).

30 Roberts, “Between the Lines,” 705; quoting Regina Schwartz, “Introduction,” pages vii–xii in Regina Schwartz, ed., Transcendence. Philosophy, Literature and Theology Approach the Beyond (London: Routledge, 2004), ix.

31 Roberts, “Between the Lines,” 709.

(22)

1.4 Schleiermacher on Religion 9 sis of intersubjectivity and its religious dimensions. In language typical of his early Romantic context, Schleiermacher understood sociability as an ever-in-process being of individuals and communities that takes place through an inter-subjective becom- ing, in infinite striving toward completion. That is to say, Schleiermacher’s under- standing of sociability is very much like religion’s “more” and “really real” as I sum- marized it from Orsi and Roberts above.

Romantic language (and its Idealist back- and foregrounds) notwithstanding, the empirical nature of sociability should not be lost: Schleiermacher at least took himself to be outlining a theory of basic human interrelationality based strictly on description of human experiences. Every subject or person experiences life under conditions of his or her own incompleteness, in its various forms – from inabilities to provide for one’s needs to inadequate explanations of one’s experience, and so on. In response, persons form relationships and communities with one another, in which each one’s uniqueness in relation to others can potentially fill out what others lack; personal forms of incompleteness can be mutually completed in relationships with others.

In these exchanges, ethical dynamics like voluntariness, mutuality, equality, tol- erance, perseverance, and freedom come immediately into play. But these qualities are not only natural dynamics of human sociability broadly, for Schleiermacher; they also play a crucial role in his theory of religion where the integration of these ethi- cal dynamics forms what Schleiermacher regards as the purest (in the sense of “most basic”) form of religious community. Experiences of success and failure in filling up one’s (or one’s group’s) experiences of incompleteness – whether in an explicitly

“religious” context or not – generate evolving senses for what is good, true, and, ul- timately, real. And this is religious territory for Schleiermacher. In more Schleierma- cherian language, all sociable relationships cultivate understandings (for individuals and groups) of self, of the nature of experience, of world, and some concept of total- ity – comprehensive, integrated understandings of self and one’s fit in the vastness of all things.

This interesting, if tense, co-incidence of actual (being) and speculative (becom- ing) makes Schleiermacher helpful for thinking about religious formation and per- sonal relationships. As already indicated, on the one hand, he understands sociability very experientially. Sociability is just practical, experiential exchange of resources among individuals that negotiates individual and social development; as such, it is also wholly historical. On the other hand, the “values” that sociability requires inev- itably orient persons toward what he regarded as essentially religious wonder and longing, namely, contemplation of the infinite and the relationship of humanity to it.

When sociability is conducted voluntarily, with mutuality, and in perseverance it de- mands commitment further to freedom and equality of participation by all. It also de- mands appreciative tolerance for others based in recognition of one’s incompleteness and need for others. And this opens one to the infinite: While discrete aims or projects may be “completed,” the structure of sociability itself is one of inexhaustible incom- pleteness stemming from essential openness to ever-new possibilities of understand- ing and embodying human life. In this way, Schleiermacher’s theory invites scholars to consider afresh the nature of religion itself and ways in which personal relation- ships might be inherently religious.

(23)

10 Chapter 1: Introduction

1.5 Project Overview: Sociability in Schleiermacher, Sociability and Religious Formation, Sociability as Intentional Practice

The combined experiential and speculative qualities of Schleiermacher’s theory of sociability make placing and understanding the concept in Schleiermacher an im- portant and complex task. Chapters two through five address the question of how to place the concept of sociability in Schleiermacher historically and systematically.

The first step of my project in chapter two, “Sociability,” is to situate Schleier- macher in a tradition. By the time Schleiermacher takes it up, the concept of Gesel- ligkeit was understood with much of the nuance for which Schleiermacher found it appealing: Sociability took on the experiential element of conversation from the early Enlightenment, the notion of mutual complement was present in popular lit- erature, even a sense of the completion of humanity through sociability emerges in moral weeklies, and by the late Enlightenment sociability is seen to help facilitate this completion to some extent.

What Schleiermacher uniquely contributes to this tradition, it seems to me, is his fusion of the importance of sociability in human development to his anthropology.

In chapter three, “Sociable Humanity,” I read two early works from Schleiermacher, namely, his Notes on Aristotle and the essay “On the Highest Good.” These con- tain his first ruminations on sociability and his first brief outline of an anthropology.

I argue that from this very early point Schleiermacher proposes a fully sociable an- thropology: to be sociable, in the way Schleiermacher understands that concept, is what it means to be human. Identification of the absolute fusion of sociability and human nature in Schleiermacher sets the stage for the remainder of the project ex- ploring experiential sociability, on the one hand, and its speculative orientation to- ward the realization of human completion, on the other, by laying the foundational claim: Wherever we find sociability in Schleiermacher, we are likely seeing him re- flect on human nature, and wherever we find humanity in Schleiermacher, we are likely seeing him reflect on the nature of sociability.

The interrelationship of sociability with Schleiermacher’s anthropology calls for a careful treatment of each concept. Chapters four and five, “Free Sociability” and

“The Sociable Society,” examine Schleiermacher’s first presentation of a theory of freie Geselligkeit and his first lectures on ethics, respectively. In the 1799 essay “Ver- such einer Theorie des geselligen Betragens”, the purpose of “free sociability” is to assist individuals in discovering “humanity,” while its telos is the completion of hu- manity at individual and universal levels.32 It is a highly speculative goal with a very

32 Friedrich Schleiermacher, “Versuch einer Theorie des geselligen Betragens,” parts. 1 and 2, Berlinisches Archiv der Zeit und ihres Geschmacks 5 (1799): 48–66 and 111–123; 1 (February 1799):

111–123. Friedrich Schleiermacher, “Versuch einer Theorie des geselligen Betragens (1799),” pages 163–184 in Günter Mecken stock, ed., Schriften aus der Berliner Zeit 1796–1799, KGA I/2 (Berlin:

de Gruyter, 2011). Two English Translations (ET) exist: Friedrich Schleiermacher, “Essay on a Theo- ry of Sociable Behavior,” pages 153–176 in Peter Foley, ed., Friedrich Schleiermacher’s Essay on a Theory of Sociable Behavior (1799): A Contextual Interpretation (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen Press, 2006) and also: Friedrich Schleiermacher, “Toward a Theory of Sociable Conduct,” pages 22–

40 in Friedrich Schleiermacher’s ‘Toward a Theory of Sociable Conduct’, and Essays on its Intellec- tual-Cultural Context, trans. by Jeffrey Hoover, ed. by Ruth Richardson, New Athenaeum / Neues

(24)

Index of Subjects

Anthropology 35, 44–51, 57 f., 77, 87, 91, 106, 109, 116, 127, 140, 143, 154, 161, – Cultural Anthropology 5166

– Intersubjective Anthropology 7 f., 35, 41–43, 48 f., 57, 82, 128, 166 – Philosophical Anthropology 41 – Sociable Anthropology 10, 13, 20, 27 f.,

32 f., 41, 143

– Theological Anthropology 54 f.

Art 24, 26 f., 30, 32, 60, 84, 99, 106, 141 – Artist 128

Association 15–17, 98, 116, 123 f., 129, 145 Assoziation 15

Awareness 7, 11, 43, 46 f., 58, 85, 92, 141, 154, 156, 166, 174

– Religious Awareness 11, 179

– Self-awareness 3, 12, 24, 126, 128, 169, 179

Beauty 25–27, 66, 129 Beneficence 2, 42–44

see also German Wohltätigkeit Beseelung 91, 159

Bewußtsein [sic] 127

Bildung 24, 30, 58, 96–98, 109, 132, 138, 147Selbstbildung 133

Community 5, 9, 11 f., 17, 20, 29, 31, 33, 36, 39 f., 44, 50, 57, 63, 67 f., 77, 81–85, 88, 93, 96–99, 102, 107, 113, 116–119, 122, 128 f., 131, 133, 135, 139, 143 f., 150–153, 157, 159–161, 164, 166 f., 169 f., 173–178

Communion 17, 118, 135, 155, 158, 174 Congregation 38, 124, 135, 162–165, 174 f.

Consciousness 101, 110, 124 f., 128, 130, 151–158

– God-consciousness 157 f.

Cosmology 5, 111

Creation 15, 84, 108, 122 f., 158, 177

Darstellung 23, 110, 128, 138

Dependence 5, 12, 19, 43, 47, 80, 83, 90 f., 107, 173 f., 176, 179

– Absolute Dependence 156–158 Development 3 f., 5, 9–11, 13, 15–18, 20,

27, 30, 32, 38–40, 47 f., 52, 55–57, 61 f., 69, 76, 78, 80–82, 87, 93 f., 98, 116, 119, 122, 125, 127, 141, 143, 154

– Individual Development 2 f., 14, 64, 83 f., 127–129, 147

Duty 15, 42 f., 66, 70, 126 see also German Pflicht – Moral Duty 63

Education 2, 14, 16 f., 20, 22, 24–28, 30, 36, 52 f., 55, 67, 77, 176

Eigenthümlichkeit [sic] 44, 83, 100, 119, 127, 131, 137

Empfindung 42 f., 47, 155

Enlightenment 10, 14, 17, 20, 27 f., 30, 52, 54, 79

Essence 21, 30 f., 48 f., 56, 61, 64, 80, 122, – Divine Essence 160164

– Essence of Religion 111, 114, 116 f., 155 – Essence of Society 56

– Human Essence 18 f., 33, 49, 61, 64, 75, 124 f., 129, 131

Eternal Life 136, 139

Ethics 37, 40 f., 51 f., 55 f., 62, 74, 76–79, 81 f., 84–96, 100–102, 107 f., 126, 136, 140, 143–145, 155–158, 169, 171 f., 178 see also Morality

see also German Vollkommenheit – Ethics of Human Completion 47 f., 92,

140, 149 f., 154, 166, 178

– Ethics of the Highest Good 76, 79, 106, – Eudaemonism/Eudaimonistic Ethics 80, 110 – Philosophical Ethics 76, 87, 94, 144, 15486 Vollkommenheitsethik 47

(25)

196 Index of Subjects Experience 2 f., 5–9, 17, 21, 25, 30, 33, 36–

38, 40, 43–47, 49–51, 58–69, 72, 75–77, 79 f., 84–86, 89, 101, 105–108, 110–116, 124–127, 130 f., 140, 142, 147, 149, 152, 155–159, 177

Fate 21, 25, 125, 148

Force 6, 25, 71, 110, 115, 133, 171 Freedom 2 f., 6, 9, 11, 17, 20, 25, 27, 41,

44–49, 57, 66, 70, 72, 77, 82, 84 f., 87–

89, 92, 102, 106 f., 110, 120–124, 126 f., 129, 131, 134, 136, 138 f., 143, 148, 150, 156 f., 169, 171–174

– Individual Freedom 40, 81, 99, 101, 111, 124, 173

– Necessary Freedom 120

Friendship 1 f., 5, 19 f., 28, 30, 40, 42–44, 57 f., 84, 93, 96 f., 100, 129 f., 134 f.

Geselligkeit 2 f., 8, 10, 12–24, 26–33, 42 f., 46, 52–56, 59, 80 f., 93, 97, 115 f., 130, 146 Gesellschaft 14, 18, 26, 66

Gesetz 69 Gleichheit 19

God 5, 21, 37, 40, 105, 115, 138, 152, 157, 159 f., 161, 163–165, 170, 174 f., 177 – Divine Essence 160

– Divine Revelation 19 – God-consciousness 157 f.

– Higher Order 27, 37, 40, 47

Good 1 f., 10, 23, 27, 30, 35, 40–42, 46–49, 51, 58, 64, 69, 76, 79, 81 f., 84, 86–89, 91 f., 94, 97, 106, 110, 126, 143, 149 f., 153, 155, 174

Grace 5, 37, 147, 166 f.

Humanity 9 f., 20, 22 f., 37, 40, 47, 51, 56, 62–68, 70–72, 82, 84–89, 91 f., 100 f., 107–113, 115–119, 122–134, 149–151, 153see also German Menschheit

– Completion of Humanity 2 f., 10–14, 19–

21, 25–27, 32 f., 35, 41, 49, 58 f., 65, 67, 78 f., 99, 106, 112 f., 131 f., 137–145, 152, 154, 159, 166 f., 169

– Education of Humanity 2, 14, 27, 67 – Higher Being 43, 58, 92, 120, 136, 150 f.

Ideal 4, 9, 14, 16, 18–21, 26, 30 f., 41 f., 46 f., 49, 73, 80, 82, 84–86, 108, 114, 117, 121, 132, 135, 153

– Idealism 86, 90, 109, 132

Impulse 5, 16 f., 25, 31, 35, 83, 87, 92, 102, 118 f., 121, 140, 174 f.

– Play impulse 25 Individuum 77

Interiority 4, 6, 15, 113 f.

Key 139, 161–163, 165, 170 f.

see also German Schlüsselamt – Office of the Key 12, 139, 142, 154,

159–167, 170 f.

– Theology of the Key 172 f.

Law 49, 51, 60–62, 64 f., 68 f., 79 f., 87–90, 93, 126, 128, 149, 162, 164

see also German Gesetz – Formal Law 69 f., 72 f., 75, 80 f.

– Material Law 69 f., 72 f., 75, 80 f.

– Moral Law 86, 126

– Quantitative Law 69–75, 81, 84 Leben 15, 63, 81, 136

Lebensart 32, 60, 63, 74 Leib 87, 91, 122

Liebe 132–136, 150, 155, 174

Love 5, 19, 30, 40, 60, 100, 102, 109, 127, 130, 132 f., 135, 137 f., 150 f., 155, 159, 174see also German Liebe

Manier 70, 84, 93 f., 101

Mensch 23, 58 f., 86–88, 91, 110, 113, 116, 122, 144, 150, 157

Gottmensch 152

Menschheit 24, 58 f., 66, 88 f., 109–111, 116, 119, 122, 124, 129, 131, 136, 150 see also Humanity

Miteinander 15 Mittwochsgesellschaft 28 Monad 48, 115

Morality 17, 20–23, 44 f., 55, 62, 73, 80 f., 88, 97, 111

Nature 1, 3 f., 8–11, 14, 19–21, 23–27, 30, 33, 36 f., 40, 42 f., 45–48, 60 f., 65 f., 69, 80 f., 82–84, 85, 87–93, 94, 100, 102, 106 f., 109 f., 111 f., 113, 115 f., 121 f., 128, 130, 135–138, 141, 144, 147 f., 150, 154 f., 169, 178

– Human Nature 1, 10–12, 14, 25 f., 30, 51, 61, 75, 80, 89, 91–93, 102, 109, 113, 124, 126 f., 129, 144, 147–150, 157–160, 164

(26)

Index of Subjects 197 Necessity 6, 12, 14, 20, 40 f., 44–47, 49,

56 f., 72, 79, 82, 85, 87 f., 91, 95, 99, 101 f., 106, 114, 120–124, 126, 129, 134, 136, 138, 148 f.

– Natural Necessity 27, 87, 92 – Necessary Freedom Öffentlichkeit 17

Ontology 7, 42, 46, 57, 85 f., 163 Perfection 14, 17–27, 32, 47–49, 51, 56,

61 f., 64 f., 75, 79, 92, 99, 111 f., 119, 127–129, 131 f., 135–138, 144 f., 148, 151, 153, 157 f.

see also German Vollkommenheit/Vollen- Persönlichkeit 81dung

Pflicht 42

Philosophy 27, 30 f., 35, 38 f., 46, 51 f., 55, 86 f., 89 f., 111, 147

– Idealism 86, 90, 109, 132

– Metaphysics 7, 42, 57, 61, 86 f., 108, 111, 132

– Moral 2, 17, 20–24, 27, 30, 42, 44 f., 55, 62–64, 73, 80–83, 86, 88, 97, 102, 111, 126, 175

– Natural Philosophy 87 – Realism 86, 108 f., 132

– School Philosophy (also German Schul- philosophie) 27

– Symphilosophy 31 f.

– Systematic Philosophy 63

Physics 3, 6, 21, 30, 73, 79 f., 85 f., 89 f., 110, 123, 137, 149, 177

Pietism 16 f., 19 f., 27, 36 Piety 16, 18, 28, 36–38, 147, 155 f.

Poetry 27, 30–32, 38

– Sympoetry (also German Sympoesie) 31 f.

Universalpoesie 27, 30, 31

Power 2, 4, 6, 44 f., 62, 64, 81 f., 91, 114, 125, 141 f., 158, 161, 163–165, 170–173, 175

Reality 4–8, 21, 31, 33, 37, 40, 59, 61 f., 69 f., 75 f., 82–84, 88, 90 f., 94, 103, 106 f., 111, 116, 122, 141, 150 f., 159, 166, 169, 172, 174

– Realism 86, 108 f., 132 – the More 6 f.

– the Really Real 6–9

Reciprocity 2, 11, 13 f., 24–27, 40–42, 45, 49, 51, 54–56, 64–75, 80, 83 f., 92, 97, 99, 101 f., 107, 109, 115, 118, 134–136, 140 f., 143, 151–153, 157, 159, 164–166, – see also German Wechselwirkung175 Redemption 12, 139, 142, 144–155, 157–

161, 166 f., 169 f., 172 f., 175–179 Relationality 1 f., 5, 9, 20, 42, 54 f., 57, 65,

85, 105, 109, 141 Revelation 19, 27, 36 Romanticism 27 f., 30, 53

Salon 13, 28–30, 32 f., 41, 53, 56 f., 79 Schlüsselamt 154, 159

Schmerz 44

Science 15, 31 f., 52, 79 f., 84 f., 89, 91, 93–96, 141

– Natural Science (also German Naturwis- senschaft) 81, 85 f., 89, 90 f.

– Physics (also German Physik) 85 f., 89 f., 110Wissenschaft 15, 31, 66, 89

Seele 87, 91

Sense 7, 10 f., 14, 25 f., 33, 43, 47, 79, 107 f., 111, 114, 129, 132, 134 f., 137, 141, 148, 155, 178 f.

– see also German Sinn Sensitiveness 132, 155 see also German Sinn Sentiment 30, 42–44, 65 – see also German Empfindung – Social Sentiment 43 Sinn 132–135, 150, 155, 174

Sitte (also German Sittlichkeit and sittlich) 54, 62, 80

Sittenlehre 94 f., 143

Sociability 2–4, 6, 8–12, 14, 18, 20 f., 23, 26 f., 30, 33, 39 f., 43–45, 49, 55–58, 60, 71 f., 74 f., 77, 80, 114–116, 169, 178 f.

– Free sociability 11 f., 15, 17, 32, 35, 41 f., 49–52, 55 f., 58 f., 61–70, 73–75, 77–79, 81, 84, 88, 93–103, 105–109, 140–145, 151–153, 171, 173–175, 177 f.

Society 1, 4, 10 f., 14–16, 18 f., 21, 26, 28, 30, 39, 49, 51, 54, 56, 61–66, 68 f., 71–

73, 77, 80 f., 84, 99, 105–107, 115, 118, 122, 151 f., 161, 170

Sphäre 44, 69 f., 84, 95 f., 100

Sphere 44–46, 59, 66, 69 f., 72, 94, 98–100, 159, 164, 167

(27)

198 Index of Subjects see also German Sphäre

– Common Sphere 15, 56, 70 f., 75, 78 f., 84, 93, 97, 100–102, 115, 131, 143, 152, 155, 160

– Sphere of Experience 44, 50, 58, 77, 106, 114, 158

– Unique Sphere 70, 96 f., 101, 152 Spirituality 5, 37 f., 40, 122, 129, 135, 164,

176 f.

System 38, 43, 47 f., 51, 55, 57, 60 f., 64, 76, 78 f., 81, 85–87, 89 f., 92–94, 96, 100–

102, 111 f., 120, 145, 159 Systemkonzeption 76

Telos 10, 12, 26, 41, 49, 61 f., 66, 78, 111 – Transcendental Telos 49

Theology 3 f., 16, 28, 52, 105, 138 f., 142–

146, 153 f., 156, 158, 160 f., 166, 171–

173, 175–179 Trieb 25

Universe 35, 57, 67, 75, 79, 82, 86 f., 90,

107–113, 115–118, 124 f., 131 f., 140, 157, 169, 179

Urtyp 138 Vergnügen 44 Vernunft 91

Vollkommenheit/Vollendung 19–21, 92, 127–129, 131 f., 137 f., 149

see also Ethics

Wechselwirkung 24–26, 56, 64–66, 92 Weltkinder 18 f.

Kinder Gottes 18 Wohltätigkeit 42

World 9, 16, 18 f., 23, 35, 37, 40, 51, 58–61, 72, 80, 85, 94, 106 f., 109 f., 112 f., 120–

126, 129 f., 134–136, 138 f., 151, 155, 157 f., 177

– Natural World 110, 134 Wissenschaft, see Science Zweck 62

(28)

Index of Names

Adam, Wolfgang 14

Aristotle 1–3, 10, 35, 41–49, 57 f., 86 f., 91, 106 Arndt, Andreas 56, 76 f., 88

Barth, Karl 105, 142 Barth, Ulrich 120, 130

Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb 2 Beiser, Frederick 26, 29 f., 54 Beßler, Ignatius 28

Beyer, Johann Jacob 39

Birkner, Hans-Joachim 52, 54, 76, 89, 94 f.

Böckh, August 76, 81, 155 f.

Bonhoeffer, Dietrich 142, 173–177 Brandt, James M. 91

Braun, Otto 52, 76 Brecht, Martin 16 Brunner, Emil 105 Calvin, John 162 f., 165 Christ, Johannine 153 Clancy, Timothy R. 55 Davies, Martin L. 30, 55 DeCort, Andrew 174 Dilthey, Wilhelm 35, 146 Dole, Andrew 105, 113 f., 117 f.

Dülon, Friedrich Ludwig 145

Eberhard, Johann August 42, 47, 49, 57, 61, 92, 147

Ehrhardt, Christiane 133 Feil, Michael 95 f., 100

Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 28, 31, 56 f., 66, 90, 109, 111

Foley, Peter 54, 56 f.

Francke, August Hermann 16, 19 Freßer, Ignatius Aurelius 72 Froese, Victor 48

Furey, Constance M. 4 f.

Gadamer, Hans-Georg 105

Garaj, Patrik 53 f.

Gaß, J. C. 145 f.

Gellert, Christian Fürchtegott 20–23, 27 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von 20, 22–24,

27 f., 38

Goosen, Rachel Waltner 172 Grunow, Eleonor 129 f.

Habermas, Jürgen 15, 54 Hector, Kevin 62, 160

Helmer, Christine VII, 96, 105, 142, 165, 177–178, 187

Herms, Eilert 46, 76, 85, 89, 91 f., 96 Herz, Henriette 28 f., 31, 74, 120, 129 f.

Herz, Markus 28 f., 31 Hinrich, Wolfgang 55

Hoover, Jeffrey 55, 63, 95–97, 130 Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich 28, 86 Jørgensen, Poul Henning 89, 91 Jungkeit, Steven 133, 146

Kant, Immanuel 2, 13, 27 f., 31, 35 f., 38, 42, 46, 48 f., 56 f., 73, 81, 86, 111, 122, Knigge, Adolph Freiherr 59–61, 72126

Landfester, Ulrike 53 f.

Lange, Samuel Gotthold 18 f.

Leberecht, Peter 32

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 27 f., 32, 47–49, 51, 61, 64, 127

Louden, Robert B. 95, 97 Luther, Martin 17, 142, 162 f.

Mariña, Jacqueline 82 Maritain, Jacques 5 Maritain, Raïssa 5 Mauser, Wolfram 15, 19 Mehra, Marlis 22

Meier, Georg Friedrich 18 f.

McBride, Jennifer 142, 169 f., 173, 175–177

(29)

200 Index of Names McCutcheon, Russell 105

Mielke, Christine 53 f.

Miller, Marlin E. 171 Moore, Brenna 4–6 Moxter, Michael 48

Niebuhr, Richard R. 135, 144, 147, 149 Nowak, Kurt 28 f., 36, 42, 56, 59 f., 109, 149 Oberdorfer, Bernd 43, 49, 54, 57, 73 Okely, Samuel 39, 129 f., 137 Orsi, Robert A. 4–9

Paul, Jean 32 Peter, Emanuel 17–19 Proudfoot, Wayne 105 Pui-Lan, Kwok 133 Reinhardt, Hartmut 24 Richardson, Ruth 146–148 Richter, Cornelia 55

Rousseau, Jean-Jacques 56, 97 Scheliha, Arnulf von 82

Schiller, Friedrich 2, 14, 24–27, 29, 56, 64, 66 f., 74

Schlegel, Friedrich 27 f., 30–33, 74, 117, Schleiermacher, Carl 36129

Schleiermacher, Charlotte 29, 36 Schleiermacher, Friedrich 2–4, 8–18, 20,

23–33, 35–49, 51–74, 75–103, 105–140, 141–161, 163–167, 169–171, 174, 178 f.

Schleyermacher, Elizabeth Maria Kathari- na 36

Schleyermacher, Johann Gottlieb Adolph 36 Schmidt, Sarah 64, 77

Schwarz, Friedrich H. C. 132 Sinn, Christian 53 f.

Sockness, Brent W. 93, 95, 119 f., 133 Spener, Philipp Jakob 16 f.

Spinoza, Baruch de 28

Thomasius, Christian 14 f., 19 f., 27 Tice, Terence N. 146–148, 150 Tieck, Ludwig 32

Varnhagen, Rahel Levin 29 Veit, Dorothea Mendelssohn 29 Vial, Theodor 62 f.

Ward, Graham 53, 55 Wolff, Christian 27, 42, 47 Yoder, John Howard 142, 169–173 Zwingli, Huldrych 163

Referenzen

ÄHNLICHE DOKUMENTE

In compiling these stages together, then, this book seeks to recon- struct Caputo’s œuvre according to the analytic of ‘sovereignty and the event’; beginning in his

novativen Ansätzen theologischen Denkens gesucht. Kauf mans Ansatz einer Theologie als „imaginative construction“ stellt mit seinem radi- kalen, konstruktivistischen Verständnis

And, simultaneously, we dis- cover some of the deep structures of modern philosophy that are prefigured in Luther, whether we read Kant or Fichte, Hegel or Schelling, Kierkegaard

Second, there are issues of personal and social life: Is it true that love and compassion enable more fulfilling and meaningful kinds of human relations than do liberal notions

Denn – und das ist die These dieser Arbeit – die in Lindbecks Buch “The Nature of Doctrine” zur Anwendung kommenden Auffassungen von Religion, Dogma und Theologie eignen sich

Liest man das Verhältnis der klas- sischen deutschen Philosophie zum Judentum aus dieser begrifflichen Perspek- tive, so zeigt sich gerade eine Vielschichtigkeit und

Angesichts dessen stellt sich die Frage, ob die Wahl der attention als Leit- begriff der Interpretation das Projekt nicht zusätzlich erschwert: Handelt es sich um einen

Indem der christologische Impetus des Konzils von Chalcedon (451) eine ontologische Kommunikationsform als Urquell des Sprechens und dra- matischen Tuns Jesu