• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

Epistemological reasoning is an important part of economic research. This fact is not yet adequately reflected in the typical structure of economic research papers which usually do not discuss epistemological issues explicitly. Given the important practical implications of epistemological orientations, this is a very unfortunate state of affairs.

To illustrate this practical relevance of epistemology we have looked at significant changes of the epistemological orientation in development economics in the recent past. The changes from realism to instrumentalism and back that have taken place created the need for methodological innovations since different epistemologies fit to different methodologies.

Given the current tendency towards mechanism-based explanations, we have discussed two different methodological reactions that could accompany this epistemological shift, at least for macroeconomics: on the one side, New Keynesian economists argue for the use of more sophisticated DSGE models, while many complexity economists favour the use of agent-based models.

Both approaches represent a movement towards a more realist assessment of the economy, but they differ in the extent of this movement: The New Keynesian approach remains much more in the realm of neoclassical economics than the complexity approach.

As in this case, where members of the respective research community are very critical of the methods used by the others, we believe that many methodological debates in economics are at the core about epistemology: researchers prefer different methods because they differ in they way they compare the quality of theories and in their strategy to make their models meaningful.

Therefore, a more explicit epistemological debate could advance many of the deadlocked dialogues among competing research communities. Such a dialogue could also help identi-fying differences in ideology that may also explain the difficult relationship among various research communities. Such hidden ideologies can be identified through an epistemological

debate and their influence could - hopefully - be reduced. 18

Beyond this clarification the paper highlighted a number of meta-theoretical concepts that are useful for economic theorizing: we explained why an excessive focus on Occam’s razor as a mean to discriminate between competing explanations can be misleading if mechanismic explanations are sought for. Economists that aim for mechanismic explanations, and there seem to be ever more of them, should rather strive for deep explanations.

Furthermore, a more open and critical assessment of the methodological toolkit available to economists is desirable. Contrary claims that, for example, proclaim the end of methodological debate in macroeconomics and see the New Keynesian way of modeling as only viable way of doing macroeconomics (e.g. Goodfriend (2007)), are not helpful for the progress of economics. This relates to another, more abstract, implication of taking epistemological debates seriously: tolerance for different research approaches in economics is very important. Since disputes about epistemological orientations usually cannot be finally resolved within a reasonable timespan, and the example of development economics discussed above showed that there is often a back and forth between different dominant epistemologies, different epistemological orientations and their methodological implications should be tolerated within the profession (see also Dobusch and Kapeller (2012)).

Our elaborations above indicated that there is not only no ‘one correct model’, but probably not ‘one correct epistemology’. Rather, a pluralism of different epistemological (and consequently methodological) approaches must be not only tolerated but actively supported. For such a pluralism to be productive, however, it is important that epistemo-logical considerations are made more explicitly such that a productive exchange among the different approaches becomes feasible. Otherwise, an unproductive pluralism of many different, isolated communities, all with their own accepted set of models and unable to understand what is going on in other communities, will be the inevitable result.

18Of course, the set of accepted complexity reductions within a scientific community are also determined partly not only by ideology, but also by the institutions and power relations within the scientific community. Particular players have an interest that certain methodologies are considered as ‘standard’

and others are not accepted methods of research. And certain positions in the scientific system (e.g.

journal editors of heads of scientific associations) give such players the influence needed to safeguard their interests by affecting the dominant epistemology and the set of accepted research methods. Such sociological aspects of the problem were not part of the present article, but would be a most fruitful element for future research.

It is the important task of economic methodologists to support a productive pluralism by identifying the different epistemologies and to relate different research approaches to each other (see already Elsner (1986)). Arguments against such a productive pluralism, such the statement of Goodfriend (2007), not only increase the danger of theoretical and methodological lock-ins - they also make the economics profession less innovative, and in the end less successful in explaining reality - regardless of how ‘explanation’ is to be understood.

References

Barabasi, A. & Albert, R. (1999). Emergence of scaling in random networks. Science, 286, 509–512.

Blume, L. E. & Durlauf, S. N. (2006). Introduction. In L. E. Blume & S. N. Durlauf (Eds.), The economy as an evolving complex system, iii: current perspectives and

future directions (Chap. 1, pp. 1–4). Oxford University Press.

Boland, L. A. (1979). A critique of friedman’s critics. Journal of Economic Literature, 17(2), 503–522.

Boland, L. A. (2010, November). The methodology of positive economics: reflections on the milton friedman legacy, uskali mäki, editor. cambridge university press, 2009.

xvii + 363 pages.Economics and Philosophy,26(3), 376–382.

Brenner, T. & Werker, C. (2007). A taxonomy of inference in simulation models. Compu-tational Economics, 30(3), 227–244.

Bunge, M. (1962). The complexity of simplicity. The Journal of Philosophy,59(5), 113–135.

Bunge, M. (2004). How does it work? The search for explanatory mechanisms. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34(2), 182–210.

Clauset, A., Moore, C., & Newman, M. (2008, May). Hierarchical structure and the prediction of missing links in networks. Nature, 453(7191), 98–101.

Colander, D., Howitt, P., Kirman, A., Leijonhufvud, A., & Mehrling, P. (2008). Beyond dsge models: toward an empirically based macroeconomics. American Economic Review, 98(2), 236–40. doi:10.1257/aer.98.2.236

Deaton, A. (2010). Instruments, randomization, and learning about development. Journal of Economic Literature, 48(2), 424–55. doi:10.1257/jel.48.2.424

Dixit, A. K. & Stiglitz, J. E. (1977, June). Monopolistic competition and optimum product diversity. The American Economic Review, 67(3), 297–308.

Dobusch, L. & Kapeller, J. (2012). Heterodox united vs. mainstream city? sketching a framework for interested pluralism in economics. Journal of Economic Issues,46(4), 1035–1057.

Dow, S. C. (2004, September). Strucutred pluralism. Journal of Economic Methodology, 11(3), 275–290.

Elsner, W. (1986). Ökonomische institutionenanalyse - paradigmatische entwicklung der ökonomischen theorie und der sinn eines rückgriffs auf die ökonomische klassik am beispiel der institutionenanalyse („property rights“). Berlin, DE: Duncker & Humblot.

Fagiolo, G., Moneta, A., & Windrum, P. (2007). A critical guide to empirical validation of agent-based models in economics: methodologies, procedures, and open problems.

Computational Economics,30, 195–226.

Fagiolo, G. & Roventini, A. (2012, June). On the scientific status of economic policy: a tale of alternative paradigms. The Knowledge Engineering Review, 27(2), 163–185.

Farmer, J. D. (2013). Hypotheses non fingo: problems with the scientific method in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 20(4), 377–385.

Friedman, M. (1953). The methodology of positive economics. In Essays in positive economics (pp. 3–46). Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press.

Giere, R. (1988). Explaining science. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Gigerenzer, G. (2016). Rationality without optimization: bounded rationality. In L. Macchi, M. Bagassi, & R. Viale (Eds.), Cognitive unconscious and human rationality (pp. 3–

22). Combridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., Samuelson, L., & Schmeidler, D. (2014). Economic models as analogies. The Economic Journal, Accepted manuscript.

Goodfriend, M. (2007, Fall). How the world achieved consensus on monetary policy.Journal of Economic Perspectives,21(4), 47–68.

Gräbner, C. (2015). Formal Approaches to Socio Economic Policy Analysis - Past and Perspectives. Forum for Social Economics. doi:10.1080/07360932.2015.1042491 Gräbner, C. & Kapeller, J. (2015). New perspectives on institutionalist pattern modelling:

systemism, complexity and agent-based modelling. Journal of Economic Issues, 49(2), 433–440. doi:10.1080/07360932.2015.1042491

Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2016, November). Why behavioural policy needs mechanistic evidence.

Economics and Philosophy,32(3), 463–483.

Guerini, M. & Moneta, A. (2016). A method for agent-based models validation. LEM Working Paper Series,2016/16.

Haavelmo, T. (1944). The probability approach in econometrics. Econometrica,12, iii–vi, 1–115.

Hallak, J. C. & Levinsohn, J. (2004). Fooling ourselves: evaluating the globalization and growth debate. NBER Working Paper 10244.

Hayden, F. G. (2006).Policymaking for a Good Society: The Social Fabric Matrix Approach to Policy Analysis and Program Evaluation. New York: Springer.

Hedström, P. & Swedberg, R. (2005). Social mechanisms: an introductory essay. In P.

Hedström & R. Swedberg (Eds.),Social mechanisms. an analytical approach to social theory (pp. 1–31). Combridge, UK et al.: Cambridge University Press.

Hodgson, G. M. (2015). Conceptualizing capitalism. institutions, evolution, future. Chicago:

University of Chicago Press.

Hodgson, G. (2006). Economics in the shadows of darwin and marx. Cheltenham, UK, Northampton, MA, USA: Edward Elgar.

Kao, Y.-F. & Velupillai, K. V. (2015). Behavioural economics: classical and modern. The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 22(2), 236–271.

Kuhn, T. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Leijonhufvud, A. (2014). Economics of the crisis and the crisis of economics.The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 21(5), 760–774.

Lucas, R. J. (1976, January). Econometric policy evaluation: a critique.Carnegie-Rochester Conference Series on Public Policy. 1(1), 19–46.

Mäki, U. (2009a). Missing the world. models as isolations and credible surrogate systems.

Erkenntnis,70(1), 29–43.

Mäki, U. (Ed.). (2009b). The methodology of positive economics: reflections on the milton friedman legacy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Mas-Colell, A., Whinston, M. D., & Green, J. R. (1995). Microeconomic theory. Oxford:

Oxford University Press.

Massaro, D. (2013). Heterogeneous expectations in monetary {dsge} models. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 37(3), 680–692.

Miller, J. H. & Page, S. E. (2007). Complex adaptive systems. an introduction to computa-tional models of social life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Moneta, A. (2005). Some Peculiarities of the Concept of Casuality in Macroeconometrics.

History of Economic Ideas, 13(3), 57–82.

Moneta, A. & Russo, F. (2014). Causal models and evidential pluralism in econometrics.

Journal of Economic Methodology,21(1), 54–76.

Pawson, R. & Tilley, N. (1997). Realistic evaluation. London, UK, SAGE Publications.

Reiss, J. (2012). Idealization and the aims of economics: three cheers for instrumentalism.

Economics and Philosophy,28(3), 363–383.

Rodrik, D., Subramanian, A., & Trebbi, F. (2004). Institutions rule: the primacy of institutions over geography and integration in economic development. Journal of Economic Growth,9, 131–165.

Schelling, T. C. (2005). Social mechanisms and social dynamics. In P. Hedström & R.

Swedberg (Eds.), Social mechanisms. an analytical approach to social theory (pp. 32–

44). Combridge, UK et al.: Cambridge University Press.

Simon, H. A. (1981). The sciences of the artificial. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

Sims, C. A. (1980). Macroeconomics and reality. Econometrica, 48(1), 1–48.

Spiegler, R. (2011). ‘Bun can’t we get the same thing with a standard model?’ Rationalizing bounded-rationality models. Economics and Philosophy, 27(1), 23–43.

Steup, M. (2014). Epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014).

Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: the status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7(1), 1–31.

Tesfatsion, L. (2006). Agent-based computational economics: a constructive approach to economic theory. In L. Tesfatsion & K. L. Judd (Eds.), Handbook of computational

economics (Chap. 16, Vol. 2, pp. 831–880). Handbook of Computational Economics.

Elsevier.

Wadman, W. (2000).Variable quality in consumer theory: toward a dynamic microeconomic theory of the consumer. Armonk, NY, M.E. Sharpe.

Witt, U. (2001). Learning to consume - a theory of wants and the growth of demand.

Journal of Evolutionary Economics, 11(1), 23–36.

Witt, U. (2010). Symbolic consumption and the social construction of product characteris-tics. Structural Change and Economic Dynamics,21, 17–25.