• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

Victim Injurer No Liability c(ynl) =c(y∗∗) =§12 c(xnl) =§0<c(x∗∗) Strict Liability c(ysl) =§0<c(y∗∗) c(xsl) =c(x∗∗) =§12

Aggregate c(ynl) +c(ysl) =§12 c(xnl) +c(xsl) =§12

Table 5.3:Sociallyvs.Privately Optimal Care Expenditures in the Experiment

even when this comes at own expenses (see Hypothesis 5.2.4). This result is consis-tent with the extant literature on other-regarding preferences in predicting individuals’

aversions to bad outcomes especially when these affect others’ well-being. Table 5.4 suggests also that care expenditures were higher when subjects were burdened by the expected accident costs, i.e.,c(xsl)>c(xnl)for the injurers andc(ynl)>c(ysl)for the victims (see Hypothesis 5.2.1).

To assess whether these differences are significant, I compare pairwise the two dis-tributions using Wilcoxon signed rank sum tests and sign tests (see Tables 5.5 and 5.6 in Appendix 5.6). The distributions of care investments are (i) significantly different from the predicted care levels; (ii) significantly lower under the no liability rule rather than under the strict liability rule for injurers (sign test, p-value = 0.0843); (iii) sig-nificantly lower under the strict liability rule rather than under the no liability rule for victim (sign test, p-value = 0.0008). On the basis of these results, Hypothesis 5.2.1 on care choices per role under the two liability rules cannot be rejected.

To better appreciate differences in investment patterns across the treatments, Figure 5.1 plots the average investments in care measures.

Both graphs in Figure 5.1 show that subjects’ investment in care measures is higher than the predicted values. More specifically, Figure 5.1a shows that care expenditures are higher in the presence of expected liability costs, as the theoretical results predict.

Victims have spent on average §27.48 in precautions under the no liability rule against the §21.07 spent under the strict liability rule. Injurers have spent on average §20.53 in safety under the strict liability rule against the §17.01 spent under the no liability rule.

27.48 21.07

0 10 20 30

victims

17.01

20.53

injurers no liability strict liability

(a)per role

17.01 27.48

0 10 20 30

no liability

20.53 21.07

strict liability

injurers victims

(b)per liability rule Figure 5.1:Average Care Investments by Treatment

Figure 5.1b highlights the fact that on average potential victims undertook approxi-mately the same level of precautions of injurers under the strict liability rule (§21.07 spent by victims and §20.53 spent by injurers).

Figure 5.1b shows the most interesting and surprising result of this experiment:

Result 5.4.1. Under the strict liability rule, victims invest about as much as injurers.

Victims under the strict liability rule heavily invest in care measures, even if per-fectly insured. Indeed, on average, under the strict liability rule, victims invested about as much as injurers (§21.07 spent by victims and §20.53 spent by injurers). Note that in the “Victim, Strict Liability” case, (a) injurers have to pay whenever damage occurs, but (b) only victims can take actions to prevent the accident. In other words, victims are the active players and are perfectly insured against accident losses. From a theo-retical point of view, we would have expected victims to undertake zero precautions or at least less precautions than injurers in the “Injurers, Strict Liability” case. Surpris-ingly, we found that victims invested about as much as injurers. This result could have

been driven by different motivations. First, it can be interpreted as another instance of social preferences: the victims see it as unfair to make injurers loose money with such a high probability, and heavily invest in precautions in order to prevent unjust liability for injurers. Another interpretation is related to the fact that only victims suffer the damage to their property. In this case, the willingness to protect personal properties might prevail over the compensation damages. In other words, victims care about their own personal properties, regardless of the compensatory system in place in case of damages.

Considering now the no liability rule, I found the following result:

Result 5.4.2. Under the no liability rule, victims invest much more than injurers.

This is coherent with the theoretical models of accident law (Shavell, 1980). Around 40% of injurers spend nothing to avoid causing an accident. Given that injurers in this case are essentially playing a risky dictator game, this result can be seen as coherent with the standard findings in dictator games in which on average around 36% of all dictators give nothing to the recipient (Engel, 2011). These results show that injurers in the “Injurer, No Liability” case nonetheless undertake on average more than 60%

of victims’ investments in the “Victim, No Liability” case. This can be interpreted as another instance of social preferences: given that, in the “Injurer, No Liability” case, victims cannot take actions to avoid the accident, injurers feel it as unfair to make victims suffering unjust and uncompensated losses.

Furthermore, Figure 5.1a shows that care expenditures are higher in the presence of expected liability costs, as the theoretical results predict (i.e., Hypothesis 5.2.1 cannot

be rejected). Victims have spent on average §27.48 in precautions under the no liability rule against the §21.07 spent under the strict liability rule. Injurers have spent on average §20.53 in safety under the strict liability rule against the §17.01 spent under the no liability rule.

Result 5.4.3. Subjects invest more in precautions in the presence of expected liability costs. Victims undertake more precautions under the no liability rule rather than un-der the strict liability rule, and injurers unun-dertake more precautions unun-der the strict liability rule rather than under the no liability rule.

Potential injurers and victims undertake care levels even when it would be desirable to not undertake them. More specifically, we would have expected potential injurers and victims to invest in zero precautions when they were not burdened by expected lia-bility costs (i.e., under the no lialia-bility rule and the strict lialia-bility rule respectively). The results show that individuals have incentives to deviate from the zero-care equilibria (see Tables 5.5 and 5.6 for the Wilcoxon signed rank-sum tests and sign tests in Ap-pendix 5.6) suggesting that people care about the others’ monetary losses. However, when comparing the incentives to undertake care measures with and without expected liability costs, it appears that individuals are more willing to invest in care measures when these prevent a monetary loss to self rather than to others, regardless of their role in the accident. Figure 5.2 shows that the total amount of care investments of injurers under the strict liability rule and of victims under the no liability rule (“with liability costs”) is significantly greater than the total amount of care investments of injurers un-der the no liability rule and of victims unun-der the strict liability rule (“without liability

costs”), i.e.,c(xsl) +c(ynl)>c(xnl) +c(ysl)(see Tables 5.5 and 5.6 in Appendix 5.6).

20.53

27.48

0 10 20 30

with liability costs

17.01

21.07

without liability costs

injurers victims

Figure 5.2:Loss To Self vs.Loss To Others

Following these results, Hypothesis 5.2.4 under which individuals were expected to care about the others’ monetary losses at least as much as their own can be rejected.

Let us now analyze the care choices of injurers compared to the care choices of vic-tims. It has been already shown that parties do not adhere to the predicted equilibrium levels of care and that they invest more in care in the presence of expected liability costs (i.e., Hypothesis 5.2.1 cannot be rejected). The question now is whether there are differences in care investments between injurers and victims. The theoretical model predicts that injurers and victims should have the same precautionary incentives under mirrored liability rules. In other words, people should be expected to expend resources to prevent being the victim of an accident inasmuch as to prevent being the injurer of an accident.

In order to test whether the difference in care choices between injurers and victims

is statistically significant, I consider the aggregate care investments under the two li-ability rules. Hypothesis 5.2.3 states that in aggregate, under mirrored lili-ability rules, the distributions of care choices should be equal between injurers and victims. The Mann-Whitney test is performed to test this prediction. The results in Table 5.7 show that the distribution of care expenses is significantly lower under the role of injurers rather than under the role of victims (Wilcoxon-Mann-Whitney test, p-value = 0.0110 under the hypothesis thatc(xsl) +c(xnl) =c(ysl) +c(ynl)).

To better appreciate differences in investment patterns across the treatment “role”, Figure 5.3 plots the kernel-density functions of the aggregate care investments of in-jures (black line) and of victims (grey line). Figure 5.4 shows the kernel-density plots with the histogram of the aggregate care investments under the two roles.

.002 .004 .006 .008 .01 .012

0 20 40 60 80 100 120

Care Expenditure

Injurers Victims

Figure 5.3:Kernel-Density Plots of the Aggregate Care Levels per Role

The graphs in Figures 5.3 and 5.4 confirm that subjects do not act as theoretically predicted, and that the care investments are not uniformly distributed across the

treat-0 .005 .01 .015 .02

0 20 40 60 80 100 120

Care Expenditure Victims

0 .005 .01 .015 .02

0 20 40 60 80 100 120

Care Expenditure Injurers

Figure 5.4:Aggregate Care Levels per Role

ment “role”. By comparing the two kernel distributions in Figure 5.3, it can be noticed that victims tend to invest less in low care levels and more in medium-high care levels as compared to injurers’ choices. Following this result, Hypothesis 5.2.5 under which individuals were expected to care more about the others’ safety rather than own safety can be rejected.

These results are summarized as follows:

Result 5.4.4. Most subjects preferred to invest in care measures even when not bur-dened by expected liability costs, i.e., c(xnl) +c(ysl)> 0. Subjects care about the others’ monetary loss, but less than their own. Formally, subjects invest in more pre-cautions when burdened by expected liability costs, regardless of them being injurers or victims, i.e., c(xnl) +c(ysl)<c(xsl) +c(ynl).

Result 5.4.5. Subjects spend more resources to avoid suffering a loss rather than to avoid causing a loss to others. Formally, potential victims spent more resources

in precautions than potential injurers to prevent an accident, i.e., c(xnl) +c(xsl)<

c(ysl) +c(ynl).

These tests show that the distributions of care investments are different between injurers and victims. On the basis of the neuroscientific contributions and of the exper-imental literature on prosocial behavior and other-regarding preferences, individuals should be expected to undertake more precautions to prevent a monetary loss to others rather than to self (Hypothesis 5.2.4). On the contrary, the experimental results show that subjects spent more resources to avoid suffering a loss rather than causing it.

This result is coherent with the contributions on prosocial preferences which show that people care about the others’ monetary outcome, but less than their own (Engel, 2011). Nevertheless, the observation of relatively hypoaltruistic behavior in the con-text of accident prevention suggests that the valuation of others’ well-beings is highly context-dependent.