• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

1.1 Locally Covariant Quantum Field Theory

1.1.2 Observables and General Covariance

In quantum theory, observables are represented by self-adjoint elements of a unital topo-logical∗-algebraA, the algebra of observables. For mathematical convenience,Ais usually taken as aC-algebra, but for us it is more suitable to consider algebras which are gener-ated by polynomials of smeared quantum elds7, because the thermal observables used in the denition of local equilibrium are of this type. They typically cannot be represented by bounded operators.

Denition 1.1.5. We dene the category Alg whose objects are unital topological ∗ -algebras A. Morphisms are unit-preserving, continuous injective ∗-homomorphisms.

The existence of a morphismA → A0 means that A may be viewed as a subsystem of A0, i.e. morphisms represent embeddings of physical systems into larger ones.

The principle of locality expresses the idea that in the theoretical description of an experiment, the only background structure used in the construction of observables refers to a specic spacetimeMand does not make use of data from the rest of any of the larger spacetimes Nthat possibly extendM(in the sense that there is a hyperbolic embedding ψ:M→N). In a local theory, observables are therefore associated with spacetimes - and it is useful to keep in mind that in the previous example M can be an arbitrarily small neighbourhood of any point inN.

For a given quantum system, locality implies that for any globally hyperbolic spacetime M there is an object inAlg, denoted by A(M), that serves as the algebra of observables on M. Let ψ:M→N be a hyperbolic embedding. Since Ncan be seen as an enlarged

6An important example that is not globally hyperbolic is given by Anti de Sitter spacetime.

7See [Sch90] for a mathematically precise treatment.

version of M it is natural to assume that A(ψ(M))⊂ A(N). Also, in a local theory no experiment taking place inMshould depend on the spacetime structure outside ofM, so one expects a close relationship betweenA(M)andA(ψ(M)). Put dierently, one expects the assignment M7→ A(M) to behave covariantly under hyperbolic embeddings. This is close in spirit to the notion of general covariance in classical general relativity.

We can now construct a theory that is independent of any particular background space-time, if we formulate it simultaneously on all globally hyperbolic spacetimes. Only then can we judge whether the theory is constructed locally and covariantly by testing how it behaves under a change of background structure, for example the metric.

This point of view is emphasized in the following denition [BFV03].

Denition 1.1.6. A locally covariant Quantum Field Theory is a covariant functor A from Locto Alg.

A lcQFT A assigns to each spacetime M the algebra of observables A(M) for M. If there is a hyperbolic embedding ψ : M → N, functoriality means that the following diagram commutes:

M −−−−→ψ N

A

 y

 yA A(M) −−−−→ A(N)αψ .

Here and henceforth, we write αψ instead of A(ψ). In case there are two hyperbolic embeddings M→ψ N ψ

0

→M0, one hasαψ◦ψ0ψ◦αψ0. Moreover,αidM = idA(M).

While the denition captures the aspects of locality and covariance from the previous discussion, it is necessary to supplement it with additional conditions on dynamics and causality.

Denition 1.1.7. LetAbe a lcQFT.Aobeys the time slice axiom if the following holds:

for any morphism ψ:M→Nsuch thatψ(M)contains a Cauchy surface ofN, the map αψ :A(M)→ A(N) is a∗-isomorphism.

Moreover, let ψ : M → N and ψ0 : M0 → N be hyperbolic embeddings and assume that their images are space-like inN: JN(ψ(M))∩ψ0(M0) =∅. Ais said to be causal if it holds that

ψ(A(M)), αψ0(A(M0))] = 0.8

The time slice axiom is the formal statement that there exists a dynamical law which allows prediction of the behaviour of the system just by knowledge of it in a neighbourhood of any Cauchy surface. Causality, on the other hand, ensures that observables which are space-like localized are commensurable in the sense of quantum theory. As is explained in

8Given two algebrasA,A0,[A,A0] = 0indicatesAA0A0A= 0A∈ A, A0∈ A0.

[BFV03], any lcQFT that obeys causality and fulls the time-slice axiom may be viewed as a generalization of the Haag-Kastler approach to QFT in Minkowski spacetime [Haa96].

It is sometimes necessary to compare results of measurements with specic observables carried out at dierent spacetime locations9, possibly taking into account the motion of the apparatus with respect to local inertial frames. This is the main reason why in this thesis we work with locally covariant quantum eld theory; in the denition of local thermal equilibrium in a curved spacetimeM, one compares expectation values of thermal observables in M with those of the corresponding observables in Minkowski spacetime M0 [BS07]. For this purpose, a lcQFT A as such is not specic enough since it deals with algebras of observables.10 What is needed is a locally covariant denition of specic observables themselves, i.e. the notion of a locally covariant quantum eld [HW01, BFV03].

These objects can be dened as natural transformations in the following way.

Denition 1.1.8. The objects of the category Top are topological spaces, while the morphisms are continuous maps. We dene the functor

D:Loc→Top

that assigns to each objectM inLocthe space of compactly supported smooth functions D(M), equipped with the usual topology. Hyperbolic embeddingsψ:M→Nare mapped to their push forwards ψ, extended by0 outside of ψ(M).

Denition 1.1.9. Given a lcQFT A, a locally covariant (scalar) quantum eld φ is a natural transformation between the functors Dand A.

In plain terms, a locally covariant quantum eldφassigns to each globally hyperbolic spacetime M a quantum eld φM. This means that on M, φM is a distribution taking values in the ∗-algebraA(M):

D(M)3f 7→φM(f)∈ A(M).

Locality and covariance are accounted for by the properties of a natural transformation.

Ifψ:M→Nis a hyperbolic embedding, then it holds that αψ◦φMN◦ψ.

9This should be important in any statistical theory, as repetitions of measurements are done at dierent spacetime locations.

10It is an intriguing question whether a given lcQFT really describes the same physics on all spacetimes [FV11]. However, as we deal with specic elds instead of whole algebras here, this issue should not be relevant for the denition of local equilibrium.

Thusφis simply a family of quantum elds{φM}indexed by all globally hyperbolic space-times M, i.e. a master eld subject to the afore-mentioned transformation behaviour under hyperbolic embeddings. It is this viewpoint that allows comparison of the same"

measurements in dierent spacetimes, which is crucial in the denition of local equilibrium in curved spacetime.

More generally, we may consider a locally covariant (r, s)-tensor quantum eld φ. By this we mean that if e is a local frame represented by a Lorentz tetrad11 {eµ}3µ=0, then there exist locally covariant quantum elds

φMµ1...µrµ1...µs :D(M)→ A(M)

called the components ofφM in the framee, which are subject to the usual transformation law of tensors12.

Finally, it should be noted that observable quantum elds are by denition real. In the scalar case this simply means thatφM(f)M(f), where is the∗- operation inA(M) and f denotes the complex conjugate of f.