• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

Imperfect observability of skill

Two-way migration between similar countries

5.3 Welfare effects of permanent migration

5.4.1 Imperfect observability of skill

As discussed earlier, one key stylised fact that our benchmark model does not capture well is the imperfect segregation between high-skilled migrants and non-migrants in the workplace, as documented byHellerstein and Neumark(2008),Andersson, García-Pérez, Haltiwanger, McCue, and Sanders(2010),Aslund and Skans(2010). In our benchmark model the probability of a given migrant being matched with another migrant is equal to one, while the empirical studies find matching rates in excess of those that would be found under random matching, but significantly smaller than one. We now demonstrate that imperfect observability of skill leads to exactly the same outcome in our model.12

11The proof is delegated to AppendixA.21.

12Hendricks(2001) introduces the possibility of cross-matching between migrants and natives by assuming that an exogenous fraction of migrants is indistinguishable from natives.

For the sake of continued tractability we model the imperfect observability of abilities in a parsimonious and stylised way. Consider the following sequence of events. Before individuals decide about migration their abilities are revealed with probability p ∈ (0,1). Then, as in our baseline model, individuals decide whether to migrate, incurring migration costc >0, or to stay put. This decision is based on a comparison of expected incomes. Once migration has taken place, with probabilityq∈(0,1) the abilities of those whose skills have been private knowledge so far, are revealed. Finally, firms hire workers and production takes place.

Before considering a worker’s migration decision in this changed environment, we have to derive the wage schedule for workers with observable skills. The firm’s profit maximisation problem can analogously to Eq. (5.2) be written as

maxs1,s2π(s1, s2) = 2As1s2w(s1)−w(s2), (5.7) in which sl,l= 1,2, refers to the skill of a worker performing taskl= 1,2, whilew(sl) denotes the wage paid to this workers. The solution to the profit maximisation problem is given by the following lemma:

Lemma 5.4.1 If workers’ skills are perfectly observable, firms maximise their profits by hiring only workers with exactly the same skill level.

Proof Positive assortative matching of workers within firms follows immediately from the su-permodularity of Eq. (5.1), see Kremer(1993).

Using the zero profit condition as well as the result on positive assortative matching in Eq. (5.7), the wage rate of a worker with observable skill levelsis given by

w(s) =As2. (5.8)

Now it is easy to see that individuals with ex ante observable skills have no incentive to migrate, irrespective of their skill level: They are positively assortatively matched in any case, leaving them with a wage rate as given by Eq. (5.8), and by staying put they can save migration costc.

For workers whose skill is unobservable ex ante, an analogous logic to Section5.2applies: They know that with probability 1−q their skill level remains unobservable ex post, in which case a

switch from low-skill groupL, with ¯sL= ˜s/2, to high-skill groupH, with ¯sH = (1 + ˜s)/2, yields a wage gain of As/2. However, with probability q their skill level is revealed ex post and the worker earns the same wage at home and abroad. Hence, the expected wage gain of switching from group L to H amounts to (1−q)As/2. For the indifferent worker with skill ˜s condition (1−q)A˜s/2 =cmust hold, giving a migration cutoff

˜

slf= 2c (1−q)A.

Comparison to Eq. (5.4) from the benchmark model shows that a positive probability q of a migrant’s skill being revealed ex post increases the migration cutoff, i.e. reduces the incidence of migration among those with ex ante undisclosed skill levels.

We now illustrate the degree of workplace segregation predicted by our model. Consider first the probability that a randomly picked migrant would have another migrant as a co-worker under random matching. This would happen with a probability equal to the migrants’ population share, which is (1−p) (1s˜lf). Now consider the same probability predicted by the model. With probability (1−q) the migrant’s skill is private knowledge, in which case he is matched with another migrant with probability one. With probabilityq his skill is revealed ex post, and he is matched with a co-worker of identical skill. Within the relevant group of individuals whose skill has been revealed, the share of migrants is (1−p)q/[(1p)q+p], where (1p)q is the share of migrants of known skill in the overall population at this skill level, andp is the share of natives in the overall population at this skill level.

Hence, in our extended model the probability for a random migrant to be matched with another migrant is equal to

Prob(p, q) = 1−q+q

(1−p)q (1−p)q+p

,

and it is easily shown that Prob(p,0) = 1, Prob(p,1) = 1−p, and ∂Prob/∂q < 0. Hence, the probability for a random migrant to be matched with another migrant is higher than under random matching. Interestingly, for a given migrant the probability of being matched with another migrant does not depend on his skill levels. This is also compatible with the results from Hellerstein and Neumark (2008), Andersson, García-Pérez, Haltiwanger, McCue, and Sanders

(2010), and Aslund and Skans (2010), who find that workplace segregation is at most weakly related to skill levels. Summing up, we have the following result:

Proposition 5.4.2 The probability of migrants to have a co-worker who is also a migrant does not depend on their skill level, and it is furthermore smaller than one, but larger than under random assignment of workers into workplaces.