• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

End tangles in S k

Im Dokument Tangles and where to find them (Seite 105-112)

4.4 Tangles in graphs

5.1.4 End tangles in S k

To complete our proof as outlined, let any finite setZV be given. For everyzZrKchoose (Az, Bz)∈τwithzAzrBz: this exists, becausez /K. Since (K, V)∈τ, byLemma 5.1.4we have (A0, B0)∈τ for

A0:=K∪ [

z∈ZrK

Az and B0:=V ∩ \

z∈ZrK

Bz.

As desired, (A0, B0)Z= (A, B)Z(which is (Z, ZK), since (A, B) = (V, K)):

every zZrK lies in some Az and outside that Bz, so zA0rB0, while everyzZK lies inKA0 and also, by definition ofK, in everyBz (and hence inB0), since (Az, Bz)∈τ.

This proof ofTheorem 35concludes our exposition of material from [11].

We conclude the section with the remark that an end tangleτ of an infinite graphGis defined by anℵ0-block if and only if it is defined by some setXV: for ifτis defined by someXV, thenXmust be infinite, as otherwise{X, V} ∈ S would witness thatX does not define τ. But ifX is infinite then so isK:=

T{B |(A, B)∈τ} ⊇X, and we can follow the proof ofTheorem 35 to show that Kis anℵ0-block definingτ.

Example 5.1.5. Let Gbe as in Example 5.1.1, that is, a single rayv0v1. . . with endω. The same argument as inExample 5.1.1 shows thatτSk is not closed in Sk for k > 2. However, ω does induce a closed tangle in S1: the set τS1={(∅, V)}is closed inS1.

Example 5.1.6. LetGbe the infinite grid, ω the unique end ofGandτ the tangle induced byω inS=S(G). SinceGis locally finite it does not contain an ℵ0-block. Thereforeτ cannot be defined by an ℵ0-block and is thus not closed in S by Theorem 35. However, for every k∈ N, it is easy to see that τSk is closed inSk: indeed, for fixedk∈N, the size ofA is bounded in terms ofk for every (A, B) ∈τSk. Thus, for every (A0, B0) ∈Skrτ, any ZV(G) with|Z∩A0|sufficiently large witnesses that (A0, B0) does not lie in the closure of τ: if Z is large enough that |Z∩A0|>|A|for every (A, B)∈τSk, then no (A, B)∈τSkwill agree with (A0, B0) onZ.

Example 5.1.6shows that the end tangleτ of the infinite grid is not defined by a setXV in the sense of (1). Moreover, even for any fixedk∈N>5, we cannot find a setXV withXB for all (A, B)∈τSk: for everyxX the separation ({x} ∪N(x), V r{x}) lies inτSk. Thus, even the tangles thatτ induces inSk are not defined by any subset ofV. However, they come reasonably close to it: for X =V and any (A, B)∈τ, the majority of X lies in B, that is, we have |A∩X| <|B∩X|. In fact, for any fixed k ∈N, any finite set XV that is at least twice as large as max{|A| |(A, B)∈τSk} has the property that|A∩X|<|B∩X|for every (A, B)∈τSk. Therefore, even though no τSk is defined by a XV, we can for each k ∈N find a (finite)XV which ‘defines’τSk by simple majority.

To make the above observation formal, for an end tangleτ ofG, let us call a setXV adecider setforτ (resp., forτSk) if we have|A∩X|<|B∩X| for every (A, B)∈τ (resp., (A, B)∈τSk). Thus, if we have a decider set for an end tangleτ, given a separation (A, B)∈S, the decider set tells us which of (A, B) and (B, A) lies inτ by a simple majority vote. ByTheorem 35, every end tangle that is closed in S has a decider set, since theℵ0-block defining it is such a decider set. In analogy with this, we shall show in the remainder of this section that for an end tangleτ its induced tangleτSkis closed inSk if and only ifτSkhas a finite decider set. Such a finite decider set can be thought of as a local encoding of the tangle, or a local witness to the tangle being closed in Sk.

In contrast, it is easy to see that every end tangle has an infinite decider set:

Proposition 5.1.7. For any endω of Gthe end tangleτ induced byω has an infinite decider set.

Proof. For any rayRωits vertex set V(R) is a decider set forτ.

Since no end tangle ofS can have a finite decider set the existence of decider sets for end tangles is thus only interesting for finite decider sets of the tangle’s restrictions to someSk.

We shall complement this local witness of a given end tangle being closed with a more global type of witness. For this we need to introduce some notation.

The(vertex) degreedeg(ω) of an endω ofGis the largest size of a family of pairwise disjointω-rays3. A vertexvV dominatesan endωif it sends infinitely

3Here our notation deviates from that in [10], whered(ω) is used for the degree ofω.

many disjoint paths to some (equivalently: to each) ray in ω. We write dom(ω) for the number of vertices ofGwhich dominateω. An endω isundominated if dom(ω) = 0; it isfinitely dominatedif finitely many (including zero) vertices of G dominateω; and, finally, ω is infinitely dominated if dom(ω) = ∞. We will show that the category that an end ω belongs to depends just on these parameters deg(ω) and dom(ω). Concretely, we will show the following:

Theorem 36. Letτthe end tangle induced by an endωofG. Then the following statements hold:

(i) τ is closed inS if and only ifdom(ω) =∞.

(ii) τ is not closed inS but τSk is closed inSk for everyk∈Nif and only ifdeg(ω) =∞anddom(ω)<∞.

(iii) τ∩Skis not closed inSkfor somek∈Nif and only ifdeg(ω) + dom(ω)<∞.

Theorem 36will be a consequence ofTheorem 35and the following theorem, which characterizes for whichk∈Na given end tangle is closed inSkand makes the connection to finite decider sets:

Theorem 37. Let τ be the end tangle induced by an end ω of Gand letk∈N. Then the following are equivalent:

(i) τSk is closed inSk; (ii) deg(ω) + dom(ω)>k;

(iii) τSk has a finite decider set;

(iv) τSk has a decider set of size exactly k.

Let us first proveTheorem 36fromTheorem 35andTheorem 37:

Proof of Theorem 36. We will show (i) using Theorem 35 and (ii) with The-orem 37. The third statement is then an immediate consequence of the first two and the fact that an end tangle which is closed inS is also closed inSk.

To see that (i) holds, let us first suppose that τ is closed in S. Then, byTheorem 35,τ is defined by anℵ0-blockKV. It is easy to see that every vertex inKdominatesω, hence dom(ω) =∞asK is infinite.

For the converse, suppose that ω is infinitely dominated, and let us show thatτis closed inS. For every separation (A, B)∈τ every vertex dominatingω must lie inB. Therefore K:=T{B|(A, B)∈τ}is infinite and thus, as seen in the proof ofTheorem 35, anℵ0-block definingτ, which is hence closed inS.

Let us now show (ii). By (i),τ is not closed in S if and only if dom(ω)<∞. On the other hand, byTheorem 37,τSk is closed inSkfor allk if and only if deg(ω) + dom(ω)>kfor allk∈N, that is, if at least one summand is infinite.

Thus (ii) holds.

Claim (iii) now follows either from claim (i) and (ii), or directly from The-orem 37.

We will conclude this section by provingTheorem 37. For this we shall need two lemmas. The first lemma can be seen as an analogue of Menger’s Theorem between a vertex set and an end. Given a set XV and an end ω, we say that FV separatesX fromω if everyω-ray which meetsX also meetsF.

Lemma 5.1.8. Letω be an undominated end ofGandXV a finite set. The largest size of a family of disjointω-rays which start inX is equal to the smallest size of a setTV separating X fromω.

Proof. Let T be a set separatingX from ω of minimal size. Clearly, a family of disjoint ω-rays which all start in X cannot be larger than T, as every ray in that family must meet T. So let us show that we can find a family of |T| disjointω-rays starting inX.

Observe that, as ω is undominated, for every vertex vV we can find a finite set TvV r{v} which separates v from ω. Thus, for every finite set YV we can find a finite set inV rY separatingY fromω: for instance, the setS

{TvrY |vY}.

Pick a sequence of finite setsTnV inductively by setting T0 := T and picking as Tn a set of minimal size with the property thatTn−1Tn=∅and thatTnseparatesTn−1fromω; these sets exist by the above observation. LetCn be the component of GTn that containsω. ClearlyTnCn−1.

We claim thatC :=T

n∈NCn =∅. To see this, consider any vC and a shortestvX path inG. This path must pass throughTn for everyn∈N, which is impossible since the separatorsTn are pairwise disjoint. ThereforeC must be empty.

By the minimality of eachTn, the sets Tn are of non-decreasing size, and furthermore Menger’s Theorem yields a family of |Tn| many disjoint paths between Tn and Tn+1 for each n ∈ N, as well as |T0| many disjoint paths betweenXandT0. By concatenating these paths we obtain a family of|T0|=|T| many rays starting inX. To finish the proof we just need to show that these rays belong to ω. To see this, let ω0 be another end of G, and T0 a finite set separatingω andω0. SinceC=∅we have CnT0=∅ for sufficiently largen, which shows that the rays constructed do not belong toω0 and hence concludes the proof.

An immediate consequence ofLemma 5.1.8is that, for an undominated endω, every finite setXV can be separated fromω by at most deg(ω) many vertices.

In fact, we can state a slightly more general corollary:

Corollary 5.1.9. Letω be a finitely dominated end ofGandXV a finite set.

ThenX can be separated fromω by someTV with|T|6deg(ω) + dom(ω). Proof. LetD be the set of vertices dominatingω and consider the graphG0:=

GD and the set X0 := XrD. ByLemma 5.1.8 there is a set T0V(G0) of size at most deg(ω) separatingX0 fromω inG0. SetT :=T0D. Then T separatesX fromω inGand has size|T|=|T0|+|D|6deg(ω) + dom(ω).

The second lemma we shall need for our proof ofTheorem 37roughly states that, for an end of high degree, we can find a large family of disjoint ω-rays whose set of starting vertices is highly connected inG, even after removing the tails of these rays:

Lemma 5.1.10. Letω be an end of Gandk6deg(ω) + dom(ω). Then there are a set XV of k vertices and a set Rof disjoint ω-rays with the follow-ing properties: every vertex in X is either the start-vertex of a ray in R, or dominates ω and does not lie on any R ∈ R, and furthermore for any two sets A, BX there are min(|A|,|B|) many disjoint A–B-paths in G whose internal vertices meet no ray in Rand no vertex ofX.

Proof. Pick a setDof vertices dominatingω and a setRof disjointω-rays not meetingD such that|D|+|R|=k; we shall find suitable tails of the rays inR such that their starting vertices together withD are the desired setX.

Using the fact that the vertices in D dominate ω and that the rays inR belong toω, we can pick for each pairx1, x2of elements ofD∪ Ranx1x2-path in Gin such a way that these paths are pairwise disjoint with the exception of possibly having a common end-vertex in D. Let P be the set of these paths.

Now for each ray in Rpick a tail of that ray which avoids all the paths in P. LetR0 be the set of these tails andX the union of their starting vertices andD. We claim thatX andR0 are as desired.

To see this, let us show that for any setsA, BX we can find min(|A|,|B|) many disjointAB-paths inGwhose internal vertices avoidD as well asV(R0) for every R0 ∈ R0. Clearly it suffices to show this for disjoint sets A, B of equal size. So let A, BX be two disjoint sets with n := |A| = |B| and let RA,B be the set of all rays in R that contain a vertex from A orB. For each pair (a, b) ∈ A×B there is a unique path P ∈ P such that each of its end-vertices either isaorb (ifaD orbD) or lies on a ray in RA,B which containsaorb; letPa,b be theab-path obtained fromP by extending it, for each of its end-vertices that is not eitheraorb, along the corresponding ray inR up to aorb. LetPA,B be the set of all these pathsPa,b. Note that the internal vertices of each pathPa,b∈ PA,B meet none of the rays inR0 or vertices inX. We claim thatA andB cannot be separated by fewer thann=|A|vertices in

G0 := [

Pa,b∈PA,B

Pa,b;

the claim will then follow from Menger’s Theorem. So suppose that some setTV(G0) of size less thannis given. Letxandy be the number of vertices inA andB, respectively, whose ray inRA,B does not meet T. There are xy many paths inPA,Bbetween these vertices in AandB. Since these paths are disjoint outside their corresponding ray segments, each vertex ofT can lie on at most one of them. Thus ifxy>nthere must be aT-avoiding path in PA,B

whose end-vertices’ rays inRA,B also do not meetT.

Sincex+y>n+ 1 we havexy>x(n+ 1−x). The right-hand side of this inequality, as a function ofxwith domain [n−1], is minimized by takingx= 1, wherefore it evaluates ton. Thusxy>n, which shows thatTdoes not separateA andB in G0.

We can thus apply Menger’s Theorem to obtainndisjointAB-paths inG0, which are the desired disjoint paths inGwhose internal vertices avoid the rays inR0 and vertices inX: the only vertices that are contained both in V(G0) as well as in eitherX or a ray fromR0 are vertices fromAorB, which cannot be internal vertices of then=|A|=|B|disjointAB-paths.

We are now ready to proveTheorem 37:

Theorem 37. Let τ be the end tangle induced by an end ω of Gand letk∈N. Then the following are equivalent:

(i) τSk is closed inSk; (ii) deg(ω) + dom(ω)>k;

(iii) τSk has a finite decider set;

(iv) τSk has a decider set of size exactly k.

Proof. We will show (i)⇒(ii)⇒(iv)⇒(iii)⇒(i).

To see that (i) ⇒(ii), let us first suppose that deg(ω) + dom(ω)< k and show thatτSk is not closed inSk. LetD be the set of dominating vertices of ω. Since|D|= dom(ω)< k the separation (V, D) lies in Sk. By definition ofτ we have (D, V)∈τand (V, D)∈. Thus it suffices to show that (V, D) lies in the closure ofτSk inSk. This will be the case if for every finite setXV there is a separation (A, B)∈τSk with (A, B)X = (V, D)X.

So letX be a finite subset ofV. ByCorollary 5.1.9some setT of size at most deg(ω) + dom(ω) separatesXfromω. LetCbe the component ofGcontainingω. We define the separation (A, B) by setting A := V rC and B := TC. Then (A, B) is a separation ofGwith

|(A, B)|=|T|6deg(ω) + dom(ω)< k,

so (A, B)∈Sk. In fact (A, B) lies inτSk asω lives inB. Furthermore we haveXAandDB since no vertex dominatingω can be separated fromω byT. Therefore (A, B)X = (X, XD) = (V, D)X, showing that (V, D) lies in the closure ofτSk inSk.

Let us now show that (ii)⇒(iv). So let us assume that deg(ω) + dom(ω)>k. Then by Lemma 5.1.10 we find a set XV of size k and a family R of ω -rays such that every vertex of X either dominatesω or is the start-vertex of a ray in R, and such that for any A, BX we can find min(|A|,|B|) many disjoint AB-paths in Gwhose internal vertices meet neither X nor any ray in R.

We claim thatX is the desired decider set forτSk. To see this, let (A, B) be any separation in τSk; we need to show that|A∩X|<|B∩X|. Let us writeXArB := (ArB)∩X and XBrA := (BrA)∩X as well as XA∩B :=

(AB)∩X. It then suffices to prove |XArB|<|XBrA|.

So suppose to the contrary that|XArB|>|XBrA|. Note first that no vertex inXArBdominatesωas witnessed by the finite-order separation (A, B)∈τSk. Therefore, for every vertex inXArB, we have a ray inRstarting at that vertex.

Each of those disjoint rays must pass through the separatorAB, and none of them hits XA∩B. Furthermore by Lemma 5.1.10there are |XBrA| many disjoint XArBXBrA-paths whose internal vertices avoid R and X. These paths, too, must pass the separatorAB without meetingXA∩B or any of the rays above. Thus we have

|A∩B|>|XA∩B|+|XArB|+|XBrA|=|X|=k,

a contradiction since (A, B)∈Sk and hence|A∩B|< k. Therefore we must have |XArB|<|XBrA|, which immediately implies|A∩X|<|B∩X|.

Finally, let us show that (iii)⇒(i). So let XV(G) be a finite decider set for τSk. We need to show that no (A, B) ∈Skrτ lies in the closure of τSk. For this let (A, B)∈Skrτ be given; thenX witnesses that (A, B) does not lie in the closure ofτ. To see this, let any (C, D)∈τ be given. SinceX is a decider set for τ we have |C∩X| < |D∩X|, and since (A, B) ∈/ τ we have|A∩X|>|B∩X|. Therefore (A, B) and (C, D) do not agree onX, which thus witnesses that (A, B) does not lie in the closure ofτSk inSk.

Note that in our proof above that (iii) implies (i) we did not make use of the assumption that the tangle τ was induced by an end of G: indeed, every orientation ofSk that has a finite decider set is closed inSk.

For an end tangleτ that is closed in S we can say slightly more about its decider sets in Sk: for everyk∈N the restrictionτSk has a decider set of size exactlyk which is a (< k)-inseparable set. Finding these (< k)-inseparable decider sets is straightforward: such an end tangleτis defined by anℵ0-blockK byTheorem 35, and every subsetXK of sizekis a (< k)-inseparable decider set for τSk. However, having a (< k)-inseparable decider set forτSk for allk∈Nis not a characterizing property for the closed end tangles ofG: Example 5.1.11. Forn∈NletKn be the complete graph onnvertices. LetG be the graph obtained from a ray R = v1v2. . . by replacing each vertex vn with the complete graph Kn, making each vertex from the Kn replacing vn adjacent to all vertices from theKn+1 replacing vn+1. Then Ghas a unique endω; letτ be the end tangle induced by ω. Sinceω is undominatedτ is not closed inS =S(G) byTheorem 36. However, for everyk∈N, the tangleτSk has a (< k)-inseparable decider set of sizek: the cliqueKk which replaced the vertexvk ofRis such a (< k)-inseparable decider set.

Im Dokument Tangles and where to find them (Seite 105-112)