• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

7 Concluding remarks

Im Dokument The two sides of envy (Seite 32-47)

This paper develops a unified framework for the economic analysis of envy by capturing its two main forces, destructive and competitive. The role of envy in society is determined in equilibrium by the level of fundamental inequality and the endogenous tolerance threshold shaped by the quality of institutions and the strength of positional concerns.

The qualitatively different equilibria that arise in this framework are broadly consistent with the available evidence on the implications of envy for economic incentives. The

“keeping up with the Joneses” equilibrium roughly corresponds to modern economies, in which emulation is the main driver of consumer demand. The “fear equilibrium” resembles the role of envy in developing countries, where the fear of envious retaliation prevents productive investment and retards progress. The different nature of these equilibria yields contrasting comparative statics with respect to the strength of positional concerns. In the KUJ equilibrium, envy enhances production by intensifying emulation, while in the fear equilibrium it reduces output by aggravating the fear constraint.

The model sheds new light on the interplay between institutions, welfare, and economic performance. First, while better institutions can move the society from the low-output fear equilibrium to the high-output KUJ equilibrium, such change need not be welfare enhancing if it triggers the “rat race” competition. Second, transfers can be used to avoid envy-motivated destruction in equilibrium, which is in line with the evidence on the role of redistributive mechanisms in developing societies.

A dynamic extension of the model explores the evolution of the economy through differ-ent envy regimes. Starting at any initial conditions, the economy converges to the long-run KUJ steady state, driven by the decline of inequality along the transition path. This tran-sition can be delayed or accelerated by factors that affect the strength of social comparisons and the relative attractiveness of productive and destructive effort.

This paper lays a foundation for understanding the changing role of envy in the process of development. This line of research is pursued in Gershman (2011b) by incorporating the basic model in a simple endogenous growth framework, in which resources are lim-ited and productivity is driven by learning-by-doing and knowledge spillovers. As rising productivity expands the production possibilities frontier for everyone, the society experi-ences an endogenous transition from the fear equilibrium to the KUJ equilibrium causing a qualitative change in the relationship between envy and economic performance.

Appendix

τ θ <1 andY2> Y1, and Lemma 1 gives the unique second-stage equilibrium.

Proof of Lemma 2. Agent 2 is solving (10) subject to (8) and (9). Consider first the caseτ θY26Y1, in

It is strictly concave inY2, and the first-order conditions yield the following optimum:

Y2=

Again,U2is strictly concave inY2, and the interior optimum is uniquely defined by the first-order condition rY1Y2

To rewrite (A2) in terms of consumption note that if destruction takes place

Substituting this into (A2) yields (12). Next, applying the implicit function theorem to (12) gives dC2

sinceC2> θC1 and 0< dC2/dC1< C2/C1. Hence,C2d(C1) is strictly increasing and concave.

It is strictly concave inY1, and the first-order conditions yield the following optimum:

Y1=

Assumptionσ >1 is sufficient forU1to be strictly concave inY1. In particular, it can be shown by simple differentiation that the sign ofd2U1/dY12coincides with the sign ofh(x)≡ −(1+σ)x2+ξ(2σ+1/2)xσξ2, wherexp

θY2/τ Y1 andξ+ 1)/τ. Then, it is easy to show that hmax18σ <0 and so,U1 is concave underσ >1.

Note that U1 is differentiable at point Y1 = τ θY2 with dU1(τ θY2)/dY1 = ((τ 1)θY2)−σ1/K1. Hence, there are only two cases. IfY26Cb2, the global optimum is given by the interior optimum in the KUJ region. IfY2>Cb2, there global optimum is in the destructive region and it is given by the first-order condition

Finally, using (A3) rewrite equation (A6) in terms of consumption levels to get (15). Applying the implicit function theorem to (15) gives

Proof of Proposition 1. Private outputs in the KUJ equilibrium are given by (16). For this to be an equilibrium two conditions must hold: Y1KUJ>Ce1 andY2KUJ6Cb2. This yieldsk>k, where ˜˜ kis defined in Proposition 1. In the fear equilibrium private outputs are given by (17). ForY2Fto be the best response of Agent 2 it must be the case thatCb16Y1F<Ce1, which yields ˆk6k <k˜ with ˆkdefined in Proposition 1. The borderline fear equilibrium happens when τ θCb2 =Cb1, that is, whenk = ˆk. If τ θCb2 <Cb1, that is, k <k, the only possibility is the destructive equilibrium. To prove its existence note that: 1) fromˆ Lemma 2,C2d(C1) is strictly increasing and concave which implies thatC2d(C1d(Cb2))>Cb2; 2) from Lemma

3,C1d(C2) is strictly increasing and convex which implies that the inverse ofC1d at pointCb1is greater than C2d(Cb1) =Cb1/τ θ. Hence, the intermediate value theorem guarantees existence of a destructive equilibrium (C1D, C2D) such that C1D<Cb1 andC2D>Cb2. Finally, direct comparison of (A4) and (A7) shows that the slope of the inverse ofC1d is always steeper than that ofC2d, which ensures single crossing.

Proof of Proposition 2. Results for the KUJE and the FE follow directly from (16) and (17). For the DE, consider the system defining the equilibrium:

(f1C1θC2ψ[C1/(C1+θC2)]1/σ= 0;

f2C2θC1φ[(C1+θC2)/C2]1/σ= 0.

Using the equilibrium conditions, it can be shown that [DCf]−1= 1

It follows that the sign of∂C1/∂λcoincides with the sign of

Plugging this expression in the previous equation and making transformations, we get σ(θ+x) +x(1θx)

The first term is always greater than 1. The second term is increasing in x and at x= 1 simplifies to τ(1 +θ2)(1 +θ)2/[2(1 +τ)2]. The latter expression is maximized at τ = 1 in which case it is equal to (1 +θ2)(1 +θ)2/461 θ(0,1). Hence, the second term is always less than 1 and∂C1/∂λ >0.

Although the sign of∂C2/∂λis ambiguous, the sign of∂C/∂λcan be determined, as it coincides with the sign of

As above, the first term of this expression is always greater than 1, while the second is always less than 1.

Hence,∂C/∂λ >0.

For part (b), note thatDθC=[DCf]−1·Dθf and

It follows that the sign of∂C1/∂θ is determined by the sign of C2+θC1 1 main text, the sign of∂C2/∂θ is generally ambiguous.

For part (c), note thatDτC=[DCf]−1·Dτf and

with both elements positive, sinceψτ <0 andφτ <0. It follows that the elements ofDτC are negative meaning thatC1and C2 are decreasing inτ.

Proof of Proposition 3. As follows from (17), the utilities in the FE are given by UF1= In the KUJE, as follows from (16), they are

UKUJi = LetL(k) andR(k) denote the left-hand side and the right-hand side of (A10), respectively. Note that: 1) R(k) is strictly increasing and concave, 2) L(˜k) =R(˜k), and 3)Lk)> Rk). Hence, eitherL(k)< R(k)

such thatg(z)>0 iffz >z. This implies that¯ ! ¯θ(0,1), such thatL(k)< R(k) (and thus,UKUJ2 < UF2)

kk,k) iff˜ θ >θ. If¯ θ <θ,¯ ! ¯kk,k), such that˜ UKUJ2 < UF2iffk >k, which completes the proof.¯ Proof of Proposition 4. It follows immediately from (A8) thatdUF1/dk >0 sinceK1=λK =kK/(1+k).

As for Agent 2,

Differentiating with respect tokand re-arranging terms we obtain thatdUF2/dk >0 iffh(k)σk2+kδ <

0, whereδis defined in Proposition 4. Next,h(ˆk)>0 iff

Finally (A9) can be re-written in terms ofkas UKUJ1 =

Proof of Lemma 4. Using (8) and (9), rewrite (22) as v (1 +θ2) The objective function is strictly concave inT. The first-order condition for interior solution, T, is

1 +θ2

where γ2 is defined in Lemma 5. It is strictly concave in Y2 and the unique optimum is given by Y2 = 2K2)1/σ Y1, which is interior iff Y1 < Y˘1, where ˘Y1 is defined in Lemma 5, and ˘Y1 < Ye1, as direct comparison shows. This yields (23).

Proof of Lemma 6. In the KUJ case,τ θY2 6Y1, as established in the proof of Lemma 3, the optimal action of Agent 1 is (A5). Now consider the case in which Agent 2 makes a full transfer under a credible threat of destruction,τ θY2> Y1. The utility of Agent 1 is

U1= γ1(Y1+Y2)1−σ 1σ Y1

K1

, whereγ1 is defined in Lemma 5. This yields the following solution:

Y1=

where ˘Y2 is defined in Lemma 5. First, note that if the optimum is not interior in the KUJ region, that is, ifY2 >Cb2, the global optimum is determined by (A11) since the left derivative of U1 at point Y1=τ θY2 is less than the right derivative. In particular, dU1(τ θY2)/dY1 =γ1(1 +τ θ)−σY2−σ1/K1, while dU1(τ θY2+

)/dY1 = (τ θY2θY2)−σ1/K1, and, after re-arrangement, the former is smaller than the latter iffγ1<[(1 +τ θ)/θ(τ1)]σ which always holds since θ(τ1)<1 +τ θ.

Consider for concreteness only the case ˘Y2<Cb2 (the other case can be analyzed in exactly the same way) which holds if

γ11/σ < 1

θ(τ1). (A12)

Then, as follows from (A11), Y2 >Cb2 implies that the best response will be b3. If, however, Y2 <Cb2, the optimum in the KUJ region is interior and needs to be compared to the best response in the transfer region. In the former case

The left-hand side of this expression, L(Y2) is strictly decreasing in Y2, which implies that the above inequality always holds in the region ˘Y26Y2<Cb2if it holds at pointY2= ˘Y2. The latter yields condition (A13). Assume that it holds along with (A12), in which caseY1= 0 is the best response for Y2>Y˘2.

Next, consider the region ˘Y2/(1 +τ θ) 6Y2 <Y˘2, in which b2 is the best response in the case with transfer and the corresponding utility is

UFT1 = σ

Since (A13) holds and KUJ optimum is interior (that is,b1 cannot be a best response) it must be the case that in this region there exists a value ofY2 such that UFT1 =UKUJ1 . Direct computation shows that this value isYe2, as defined in Lemma 5, where ˘Y2/(1 +τ θ)<Ye2<Y˘2. So, the global optimum is the KUJ best response, ifY26Ye2, andb2, otherwise. Putting everything together yields the statement of Lemma 5.

Proof of Proposition 5. For (16) to be an equilibrium, as follows from Lemma 5 and Lemma 6, the following conditions must hold: Y1KUJ > Ye1 and Y2KUJ 6 Ye2. The former yields the condition k >

21)σ/(σ−1), while the latter leads tok>ω. As follows from the lemmas below, ω is well-defined and exceeds (γ21)σ/(σ−1), that is, a KUJ equilibrium exists iffk>ω.

Lemma A. Under the full transfer condition, τ θ 6(1θ)/(1 +θ), the parameter ω is well-defined, that is,σ(1γ11/σ)(1θ)> θ(σ1). The latter can be re-arranged as (σθ)/(1θ)< σγ11/σ. Define θ/(1θ). The right-hand side, R(a), is strictly increasing and convex in a, with R(0) = 1 = L(0), R(1) = (1 +τ θ)/(θ(τ1))> L(1), andR(0) = ln[(1 +τ θ)/θ(τ1)]. Note thatR(0) is strictly decreasing in τ and, hence, under the full-transfer assumptionτ <[1θ]/[θ(1 +θ)], infR(0) = ln[2/(1θ2)].

The latter is well-defined sinceθ <

21, as follows from the full-transfer assumption together withτ >1.

Finally, ln[2/(1θ2)] monotonically increases inθon the segment [0, afrom Lemma A, this inequality can be re-written as

1 +τ θ θ(τ1)

a

<1 + a(1 +θ) θ(τ1).

The left-hand side is a strictly increasing convex function of a, while the right-hand side is linear in a.

Moreover, the two parts coincide at the endpoint of the [0,1] segment. It follows that the above inequality holds for alla(0,1).

For (25) to be an equilibrium the following conditions must hold: Y1FT 6 Y˘1 and Y2FT > Y˘2. The former is always true, while the latter yields the condition k 6 γ21. It follows that FT and KUJ equilibria coexist iff ω 6 k 6 γ21, where ω < γ21 is the existence assumption. If k = γ21, the best-response functions partially overlap yielding a continuum of equilibria.

Finally, it can be shown that the fear equilibrium without transfers (as in the basic model) does not exist. For (17) to be an equilibrium, conditionY2F=Cb26Ye2must be satisfied, but restriction (A12) rules this out sinceYe2<Y˘2<Cb2. Putting everything together yields the statement of Proposition 5.

Proof of Proposition 6. It follows from (16) and (25) that C1KUJ

C2KUJ = k1/σ+θ

1 +θk1/σ, C1FT C2FT =τ θ.

Then, inequality is higher in FT equilibrium iffk > [(1τ θ2)/θ(τ1)]−σ, and it is sufficient to show

The functionq(a) is strictly increasing since q(a) =a which completes the proof of part 1.

It follows from (16) and (25) thatYKUJ> Y2FT iff (k1/σ+ 1)/(1θ)> γ1/σ2 . Sincek > ω, k1/σ+ 1

1θ > ω1/σ+ 1

1θ = σγ11/σ1

σ(γ11/σ1)θ(σγ11/σ1).

As can be easily shown, the right-hand side of this expression exceedsγ21/σ iff 1θ < h(a), where h(a) 1

As follows from (2), (5), and Proposition 5, in the FT equilibrium the utilities of agents are given by:

UFT1 = γ12K2)1−σσ

In the KUJ equilibrium they are given by (A9). Direct comparison shows that UKUJ1 > UFT1 iff (1 θ21γ2(1−σ)/σk >θ2)k1/σ+θ(σ1), which is the condition in Proposition 6. Similarly, UKUJ2 > UFT2

Since the left-hand side is strictly increasing in k, it is sufficient to prove that the above inequality holds at k =γ21 to establish that it holds k (ω, γ21). After re-arranging the terms, at k =γ21 the

Denote the right-hand side of this inequality asR(a). Then,R(a)>0 iff q(a)

The functionq(a) is strictly increasing since (29). The form of g3(kt) follows from (12), (15) and (29). Next, it is straightforward to establish by differentiation thatg1(k) andg2(k) are strictly increasing and concave, given thatβ <1 andσ(1β)>1.

Furthermore, 1)g1(1) = 1, 2) g1k) =g2k)>k, and 3)˜ g2k) =g3k)>ˆk. The second property holds iff τ θ > k)1−β = [θ(τ 1)/(1τ θ2)]σ(1−β) which is always trues since τ θ > θ(τ 1)/(1τ θ2) and σ(1β)>1. The third property holds iffτ θ >k)1−β which is always true, as follows from property 2 and the fact that ˆk <˜k. Together these properties imply thatkt+1> kt forkt>k.ˆ

Finally, if there exists a steady state ¯kin the destructive segment, it is given byg3k) = ¯k. Making a substitutionκ= ¯k1−β and rearranging terms yields the equation defining the steady state:

κ2−β right-hand side of (A14), is strictly increasing and convex. Also, L(κ), the left-hand side of (A14), is strictly increasing. To show that it is concave forκ > θ, note that the sign ofL′′(κ) is determined by the sign of L(κ)˜ +θ)(2β)(βκ+θ(1β))κ(32β)(βκ+θ(2β)). Atκ=θthis expression is negative, since β <1. Moreover, it is strictly decreasing for the same reason. Hence,L′′(κ)<0 forκ > θ. This implies that there exists at most one solution to (A14). If there is no solution, the proof is finished. Assume now that ¯k exists. In this case ¯k >k. To see this, note first that ˆˆ k <(τ θ)1/(1−β). Next, κ > τ θ since L(τ θ)> R(τ θ). Hence, ¯kκ1/(1−β)>(τ θ)1/(1−β)>ˆk, that is,kt+1> ktfor 0< kt<k.ˆ

Proof of Lemma 9. It follows from the properties of g1(kt) that kt monotonically converges to 1 in the KUJ region. The expression for ∆Ki = 0 comes from (30) and may be rewritten as Kjt = Kit[(ρKit1−β−1/σ 1)/θ]σ, where ρ (1θ2)/α. Then, by differentiation we get that dKjt/dKit > 0 and d2Kjt/dKit2 >0, since σ(1β)> 1. This implies the stated properties of the ∆Ki = 0 loci. The expression for ¯K follows from solving ∆K1= ∆K2= 0 and (16) then gives ¯Y.

Proof of Lemma 10. The equations for ∆Ki = 0 come from (30). Since in the fear region K1t+1 = ατ K1t1/σ+β/(τ 1) and σ(1β)> 1,K1t converges to ¯K1. Plugging this in ∆K2 = 0 yields ¯K2. The output levels follow from (17). To see that the long-run fear equilibrium is in the KUJ region, note that the implied steady-state level of inequality is [τ θ]1/(1−β) which exceeds ˜k = [θ(τ1)/(1τ θ2)]σ, since σ(1β)>1 andθ(τ1)/(1τ θ2)< τ θ <1.

Equilibria in the model with symmetric destruction opportunities. As mentioned in section 3, the assumption about “predator and prey” relationship between Agent 1 and Agent 2 is without loss of generality. Combining the proofs of lemmas 2 and 3 we get that in the general case the best responses of both agents are symmetric and have the following form:

Ci(Cj) =

It follows from the proof of Proposition 1 and the fact thatK1< K2 that the equilibria of this game in general formulation are fully characterized in Proposition 1. Figure 14 depicts the alternative equilibria under symmetric best responses (cf. figures 3 and 4).

BR2

Figure 14: Equilibria in the symmetric envy game.

References

Banerjee, Abhijit, “Envy,” in Bhaskar Dutta, Shubhashis Gangopadhyay, Debraj Ray, and Dilip Mookherjee, eds., Economic Theory and Policy: Essays in Honour of Dipak Banerjee, New York: Oxford University Press, 1990, pp. 91–111.

Barnett, Richard C., Joydeep Bhattacharya, and Helle Bunzel, “Choosing to Keep up with the Joneses and Income Inequality,”Economic Theory, December 2010, 45 (3), 469–496.

Belk, Russell W., “Marketing and Envy,” in Richard H. Smith, ed., Envy: Theory and Research, Oxford University Press, 2008, chapter 12, pp. 211–226.

Benhabib, Jess, Alberto Bisin, and Matthew Jackson, eds, Handbook of Social Economics, Vol. 1, Elsevier, 2011.

Boskin, Michael J. and Eytan Sheshinski, “Optimal Redistributive Taxation when Individual Welfare Depends upon Relative Income,”Quarterly Journal of Economics, November 1978, 92 (4), 589–601.

Bowles, Samuel and Yongjin Park, “Emulation, Inequality, and Work Hours: Was Thorsten Veblen Right?,”Economic Journal, November 2005, 115(507), F397–F412.

Cancian, Frank,Economics and Prestige in a Maya Community, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1965.

Carroll, Christopher D., Jody R. Overland, and David N. Weil, “Comparison Utility in a Growth Model,” Journal of Economic Growth, December 1997, 2 (4), 339–367.

Clanton, Gordon, “Jealousy and Envy,” in Jan E. Stets and Jonathan H. Turner, eds., Handbook of the Sociology of Emotions, Berlin: Springer, 2006, chapter 18, pp. 410–

442.

Clark, Andrew E. and Claudia Senik, “Who Compares to Whom? The Anatomy of Income Comparisons in Europe,” Economic Journal, May 2010, 120, 573–594.

, Paul Frijters, and Michael Shields, “Relative Income, Happiness and Utility:

An Explanation for the Easterlin Paradox and Other Puzzles,” Journal of Economic Literature, June 2008,46 (1), 95–144.

Clark, Anrew E. and Andrew J. Oswald, “Comparison-Concave Utility and Following Behaviour in Social and Economic Settings,” Journal of Public Economics, October 1998, 70 (1), 133–155.

D’Arms, Justin and Alison Duncan Kerr, “Envy in the Philosophical Tradition,” in Richard H. Smith, ed., Envy: Theory and Research, Oxford University Press, 2008, chapter 3, pp. 39–59.

Demsetz, Harold, “Toward a Theory of Property Rights,” American Economic Review, May 1967, 57 (2), 347–359.

Dow, James, “The Image of Limited Production: Envy and the Domestic Mode of Pro-duction in Peasant Society,” Human Organization, Winter 1981, 40 (4), 360–363.

Elster, Jon, “Envy in Social Life,” in Richard J. Zeckhauser, ed., Strategy and Choice, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991, chapter 3, pp. 49–82.

Falk, Armin and Markus Knell, “Choosing the Joneses: Endogenous Goals and Refer-ence Standards,”Scandinavian Journal of Economics, October 2004,106(3), 417–435.

Fern´andez de la Mora, Gonzalo,Egalitarian Envy. The Political Foundations of Social Justice, New York: Paragon House Publishers, 1987.

Fern´andez, Raquel, “Does Culture Matter?,” in Jess Benhabib, Alberto Bisin, and Matthew Jackson, eds., Handbook of Social Economics, Vol. 1, Elsevier, 2011, chap-ter 11, pp. 481–510.

Fliessbach, K., B. Weber, P. Trautner, T. Dohmen, U. Sunde, C.E. Elger, and A. Falk, “Social Comparison Affects Reward-Related Brain Activity in the Human Ventral Striatum,” Science, 2007, 318 (5854), 1305–1308.

Foster, George, “The Anatomy of Envy: A Study in Symbolic Behavior,” Current An-thropology, April 1972, 13 (2), 165–202.

, Tzintzuntzan: Mexican Peasants in a Changing World, New York: Elsevier, 1979.

Frank, Robert H., “The Demand for Unobservable and Other Nonpositional Goods,”

American Economic Review, March 1985, 75 (1), 101–116.

,Falling Behind: How Rising Inequality Harms the Middle Class, Berkeley: University of California Press, 2007.

and Ori Heffetz, “Preferences for Status: Evidence and Economic Implications,”

in Jess Benhabib, Alberto Bisin, and Matthew Jackson, eds., Handbook of Social Economics, New York: Elsevier, 2011, chapter 3.

Gershman, Boris, “The Economic Origins of the Evil Eye Belief,” 2011. Working Paper, Brown University.

, “From Fear to Competition: Envy in the Process of Development,” 2011. Working Paper, Brown University.

Graham, Carol, Happiness Around the World. The Paradox of Happy Peasants and Miserable Millionaires, Oxford University Press, 2010.

Grossman, Herschel I. and Minseong Kim, “Swords or Plowshares? A Theory of the Security of Claims to Property,” Journal of Political Economy, December 1995, 103 (6), 1275–88.

and , “Predation and Production,” in Michelle R. Garfinkel and Stergios Skaper-das, eds., The Political Economy of Conflict and Appropriation, Cambridge, MA:

Cambridge University Press, 1996, chapter 4, pp. 57–72.

Hopkins, Ed, “Inequality, Happiness and Relative Concerns: What Actually Is Their Relationship?,” Journal of Economic Inequality, December 2008, 6(4), 351–372.

and Tatiana Kornienko, “Running to Keep in the Same Place: Consumer Choice as a Game of Status,” American Economic Review, September 2004, 94 (4), 1085–

1107.

Knell, Markus, “Social Comparisons, Inequality, and Growth,” Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, December 1999, 155(4), 664–695.

Ljungqvist, Lars and Harald Uhlig, “Tax Policy and Aggregate Demand Management under Catching Up with the Joneses,”American Economic Review, June 2000,90(3), 356–366.

Luttmer, Erzo F., “Neighbors as Negatives: Relative Earnings and Well-Being,” Quar-terly Journal of Economics, August 2005,120 (3), 963–1002.

Matt, Susan J., Keeping Up with the Joneses: Envy in American Consumer Society, 1890–1930, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2003.

Mitsopoulos, Michael, “Envy, Institutions and Growth,”Bulletin of Economic Research, July 2009, 61(3), 201–222.

Mui, Vai-Lam, “The Economics of Envy,”Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, May 1995, 26 (3), 311–336.

Neumark, David and Andrew Postlewaite, “Relative Income Concerns and the Rise in Married Women’s Employment,” Journal of Public Economics, October 1998, 70 (1), 157–183.

Oswald, Andrew J., “Altruism, Jealousy and the Theory of Optimal Non-linear Taxa-tion,” Journal of Public Economics, February 1983, 20 (1), 77–87.

Platteau, Jean-Philippe, Institutions, Social Norms, and Economic Development, Har-wood Academic Publishers, 2000.

Robson, Arthur J. and Larry Samuelson, “The Evolutionary Foundations of Pref-erences,” in Jess Benhabib, Alberto Bisin, and Matthew Jackson, eds., Handbook of Social Economics, New York: Elsevier, 2011, chapter 4.

Rustichini, Aldo, “Dominance and Competition,” Journal of the European Economic Association, April–May 2008, 6 (2–3), 647–656.

Schoeck, Helmut,Envy: A Theory of Social Behavior, New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1969.

Schor, Juliet B., The Overworked American: The Unexpected Decline of Leisure, New York: Basic Books, 1991.

Scott, James C., The Moral Economy of the Peasant: Rebellion and Subsistence in Southeast Asia, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1976.

Smith, Richard H. and Sung H. Kim, “Comprehending Envy,”Psychological Bulletin, January 2007,133 (1), 46–64.

Solnick, Sara J. and David Hemenway, “Are Positional Concerns Stronger in Some Domains than in Others?,”American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, May 2005, 95 (2), 147–151.

van de Ven, Niels, Marcel Zeelenberg, and Rik Pieters, “Leveling Up and Down:

The Experiences of Benign and Malicious Envy,”Emotion, June 2009, 9(3), 419–429.

Veblen, Thorstein B., “Some Neglected Points in the Theory of Socialism,” Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, November 1891,2 (3), 57–74.

Wolf, Eric R., “Types of Latin American Peasantry: A Preliminary Discussion,”

Wolf, Eric R., “Types of Latin American Peasantry: A Preliminary Discussion,”

Im Dokument The two sides of envy (Seite 32-47)