• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

Balanced per capita contributions and levels structure of cooperation

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Aktie "Balanced per capita contributions and levels structure of cooperation"

Copied!
15
0
0

Wird geladen.... (Jetzt Volltext ansehen)

Volltext

(1)

Munich Personal RePEc Archive

Balanced per capita contributions and levels structure of cooperation

Gómez-Rúa, María and Vidal-Puga, Juan

Universidade de Vigo, Universidade de Vigo

9 April 2008

Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/8208/

MPRA Paper No. 8208, posted 10 Apr 2008 14:10 UTC

(2)

Balanced per capita contributions and levels structure of cooperation

María Gómez-Rúa

Departamento de Estatística e Investigación Operativa Universidade de Vigo

Juan J. Vidal-Puga

y

Research Group in Economic Analysis and

Departamento de Estatística e Investigación Operativa Universidade de Vigo

April 9, 2008

Abstract

We de…ne a new value for games with levels structure. We intro- duce a new property in this class of games, balanced per capita con- tributions, which is related with others in the literature. We provide an axiomatic characterization of this value using this new property.

Keywords:levels structure, value, balanced per capita contribu- tions.

1 Introduction

In many real situations the agents cooperate in order to get a bene…t. This situation can be modelled as a transferable utility (TU, for short) game in

Financial support from the Spanish Ministerio de Ciencia y Tecnología and FEDER through grant SEJ2005-07637-C02-01/ECON and the Xunta de Galicia through grants PGIDIT06PXIC300184PN and PGIDIT06PXIB362390PR is gratefully acknowledged.

yCorresponding author. E-mail: vidalpuga@uvigo.es

(3)

which the players partition themselves into groups for the purpose of bar- gaining. These situations are modelled as TU games with coalition structure.

However, in many situations a coalition structure does not provide a complete description of the cooperation structure.

For instance, consider the members of the European Union Parliament.

In this situation, even though all of them have the same rights, they do not act independently. The natural cooperation structure will be form by the parties. However, on a higher level, parties may associate according to their ideology in larger groups, such like the European People’s Party (EPP), the European Democrats (ED), the Party of European Socialist (PES), etc. In an even higher level, the EPP and the ED form a larger group, the EPP-ED, and so other groups. This example appears in Winter (1989), Calvo et al.

(1996) and Vidal-Puga (2005).

In these cases, a more detailed mapping of the cooperation structure is needed.

This cooperation description of the players is called a levels structure.

There are several values in the literature that take into account the levels structure. For the particular case of one single level, Aumann and Drèze (1974) …rst proposed a value for this class of games. Owen (1977) de…ned a new value, the Owen value. Both values extend the Shapley value (Shapley, (1953b)). Other extensions are provided by Hamiache (2006) and Kamijo (2007). On the other hand, Levy and McLean (1989) proposed a value that is an extension of the weighted Shapley value (Kalai and Samet (1984)).

Winter (1989) de…ned a value, the levels structure value, …rst suggested by Owen in 1977. This value is an extension of the Owen value for several levels.

Calvo et al. (1996) provided a characterization of thelevels structure value using the principle of balanced contributions. This property states that, for any two coalitions that belong to the same coalition at higher levels, the amount that the players in each coalition would gain or lose by the other’s coalition withdrawal from the game should be equal.

Nevertheless, when the coalitions represent groups of di¤erent size, this symmetry among coalitions may not be always a reasonable requirement for a value. See, for instance, Levy and McLean (1989) or Kalai and Samet (1987).

Vidal-Puga (2006) de…ned a value, for games with a unique level of cooperation taking into account the asymmetry between the coalitions due to their di¤erent size.

(4)

In this paper we extend the value for games with levels structure. More- over we introduce a new property for this kind of games,balanced per capita contributions,that is related to another property proposed by Myerson (1980) and also studied by Hart and Mas-Colell (1989), Sánchez (1997) and Calvo and Santos (2000).

The property ofbalanced per capita contributions states that for any two coalitions that belong to the same coalition at higher levels, the average amount that the players in each coalition would gain or lose by the other’s coalition withdrawal from the game should be equal. The average is taken over the number of single agents in each coalition.

A similar axiom was introduced in Herings et al. (2005) in the context of cycle-free graph games.

We also provide a characterization of the new value using this property.

The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we introduce the model.

In Section 3 we introduce a new value for this class of games. In Section 4 we de…ne the property of balanced per capita contributions. Moreover we prove that the new value satis…es this property. In Section 5 we provide a characterization of the value. In Section 6 we compare our results with those presented by Calvo et al. (1996).

2 The model

Let U =f1;2; :::g be a (may be in…nite) set of potential players.

A game with transferable utility,T U game, is a pair(N; v), whereN U is …nite and v : 2N ! R satis…es v(;) = 0: We denote by T U(N) the set of T U games withN as player set. IfS N;we denote by(S; v)the restriction of v to the player set S:

Given N U …nite, we call coalition structure on N a partition of the player set N, i.e. C = fC1; C2; ::::; Cmg 2N is a coalition structure if it satis…es S

Cq2CCq =N and Cq\Cr=; whenq 6=r: We also assume Cq6=; for all q: Given S N;we denote by CS the coalition structure restricted to S; i:e: CS =fCq\S :Cq 2 C; Cq\S 6=;g:

A levels structure for N is a sequence C= (C0;C1; :::;Ch); h 1 with Cl (0 l h) coalition structure on N such that:

1. C0 =ff1g;f2g; ::::;fngg:

2. Ch =fNg:

(5)

3. If Cql 2 Cl with 0< l h then Cql = S

S2Q

S for some Q Cl 1:

We callCl thel-th level ofC:We say thatCis a levels structure ofdegree h: Hence, the levels structure Chas h+ 1 levels.

Ifh= 1, we say that Cis a trivial levels structure.

Given Cl 2 C; we de…ne C=Cl as the levels structure induced from C by considering the coalitions in Cl as players.

Let LT U be the set of all (N; v;C) with (N; v) 2 T U(N) and C levels structure for N:When the levels structure is clear, we may write (N; v) orv instead of (N; v;C):

Denote Cl = fC1l; ::::; Cm(l)l g and let Nl = f1; :::; m(l)g. The quotient game (Nl; v=Cl;C=Cl)is the game in LT U de…ned on the coalition structure Cl with characteristic function

(v=Cl)(Q) = v [

q2Q

Cql

!

for all Q Nl:

A value in LT U is a function f that assigns to each (N; v;C) 2 LT U a vector f(N; v;C) 2 RN: As usual, fi(N; v;C) represents the payo¤ received by player i2N:

For any(N; v;C)2LT U ; a value f is e¢cient if X

i2N

fi(N; v;C) =v(N):

One of the most important values in TU games is the Shapley value (Shapley (1953b)). We denote the Shapley value of the TU game (N; v) as Sh(v)2RN:

A nonsymmetric generalization of the Shapley value is theweighted Shap- ley value (Shapley (1953a), Kalai and Samet (1987, 1988)). Given a vector of weights! 2RN++; we denote the weighted Shapley value asSh!(v)2RN.

3 A new value

Winter (1989) de…ned the levels structure value (LSV), that is an extension of the Owen value for this kind of games.

(6)

One of the properties that satis…es theLSV iscoalitional symmetry (Win- ter, 1989, page 229). This property ensures that if two coalitions are symmet- ric in the quotient game and furthermore they belong to the same coalition in the next level, their members should receive the same aggregate amount.

There are several authors in the literature that claim that when the coalitions represent groups of di¤erent size, this symmetry may not be a reasonable re- quirement. See, for instance, Levy and McLean (1989) or Kalai and Samet (1987). In particular, the latter claimed that in this case, it seems reasonable to assign a size-depending weight to each coalition.

The value presented by Vidal-Puga (2006) for TU games with coalition structure takes this idea into account.

Now we extend the value for games with levels structure. The intuitive idea of this value is as follows: In a …rst stage, we distribute v(N) among the coalitions of the (h 1)-th level through the weighted Shapley value with weights given by the size of the coalitions. Then, for any Cqh 1 2 Ch 1; we distribute the payment received by Cqh 1 in the …rst stage among all the coalitions inCh 2 that belong toCqh 1:Again we do it through the weighted Shapley value. At the last stage, we distribute the payment received by the coalitions in C1 among the agents.

The formal de…nition is as follows:

De…ne the TU game N; vNN h as(N; v):Assume we have de…ned the T U game (Cpk; vN kCk

p) for k > l and p 2 Nk and moreover, X

p2Nk

vN kCk

p(Cpk) =v(N).

Given q 2 Nl; we de…ne a new T U game (Cql; vCN ll

q): Take Csl+1 such that Cql Csl+1. Let T Cql: We will de…ne vCN ll

q(T): Let 2 RN++l be de…ned as

q =jTj and r = Crl for r6=q: We de…ne:

vCN ll

q(T) = Shq vN(l+1)

Csl+1 =C(Cl l+1 s nCql)[T

for all T Cql.

It follows from this de…nition and the induction hypothesis that X

p2Nl

vCN ll

p(Cpl) = v(N):

Then, we de…ne:

i(N; v;C) = vfigN0(fig)

(7)

for all i2N:

Ifh= 1;bothLSV and coincide withSh:Forh= 2;theLSV coincides with the Owen value and coincides with .

4 Balanced per capita contributions

Myerson (1980) de…ned the following properties:

De…nition 1 A valuef satis…es Balanced Individual Contributions1 (BIC) if and only if

fi(N; v) fi(Nnfjg; v) =fj(N; v) fj(Nnfig; v) for all i; j 2N and all (N; v)2T U.

De…nition 2 Let (N; v) be a TU game. Let 2 RN++. A value f satis…es -Balanced Individual Contributions2 ( -BIC) if and only if

fi(N; v) fi(Nnfjg; v)

i

= fj(N; v) fj(Nnfig; v)

j

for all i; j 2N:

Myerson (1980, Lemma 6) proved that, given 2 RN++; there exists a unique e¢cient value satisfying -balanced individual contributions.

Hart and Mas-Colell (1989) showed that this family of values coincides with the family of weighted Shapley values. See also Sánchez (1997) and Calvo and Santos (2000).

Proposition 3 (Hart and Mas-Colell, 1989, page 604): For any 2 RN++; Sh is the only e¢cient value that satis…es -BIC.

Calvo et al. (1996) extended BIC to the context of games with levels structure as follows:

1Myerson called it Balanced Contributions.

2Myerson used the equivalent notation -Balanced Contributions with = 1; where

1

i= 1i:

(8)

De…nition 4 A value f satis…es Balanced Group Contributions3 (BGC) if for all Cql; Crl 2 Cl such that Cql; Crl Ckl+1 2 Cl+1 (l = 0;1; :::; h 1); we have

X

i2Cql

fi(N; v) X

i2Cql

fi(NnCrl; v) = X

i2Crl

fi(N; v) X

i2Clr

fi(NnCql; v)

for all (N; v;C)2LT U:

This property states that for any two coalitions, Cql and Crl that belong to the same coalitions at higher levels, the contributions of Cql to the total payo¤ of the members in Crl must be equal to the contribution of Crl to the total payo¤ of the members in Cql:

Calvo et al. (1996) characterized thelevels structure value with the prop- erty of BGC.

The equivalent of -BIC for the context of the TU games with levels structure, with q = Cql for all Cql 2 Cl and all l = 0;1; :::; h 1; is the following:

De…nition 5 A valuef satis…es Balanced Per Capita Contributions (BPCC) if for all Cql; Crl 2 Cl such that Cql; Crl Ckl+1 2 Cl+1 (l = 0;1; :::; h 1); we have

P

i2Cqlfi(N; v) P

i2Cqlfi(NnCrl; v)

Cql =

P

i2Crlfi(N; v) P

i2Crlfi(NnCql; v) jCrlj

for all (N; v;C)2LT U.

This property ensures that for any two coalitions Cql and Crl that belong to the same coalitions at higher levels, the change per capita in the payo¤s of the players in Cql if Crl leaves the game should be equal to the change per capita in the payo¤s of the players in Crl if Cql leaves the game.

Proposition 6 is e¢cient and satis…es BP CC:

Proof. It is straightforward to check that is e¢cient.

Now we prove that satis…esBP CC: Fix(N; v;C)withC=fC0; ::::;Chg:

Given Ckl+1 2 Cl+1; let Cql; Crl 2 Cl such thatCql; Crl Ckl+1:

3Calvo et al. called it Balanced Contributions.

(9)

By de…nition of ; we have that X

i2Cql

i(N; v) = Shq vN(l+1)

Ckl+1 =CCll+1 k

and X

i2Cql

i(NnCrl; v) = Shq v(NnCrl)(l+1)

Ckl+1nCrl =CCll+1 k nCrl :

Hence,

X

i2Cql

i(N; v) X

i2Cql

i(NnCrl; v)

= Shq vCN(l+1)l+1 k

=CCll+1

k Shq vC(Nl+1nCrl)(l+1) k nCrl =CCll+1

k nCrl : By de…nition, vCN(l+1)l+1

k

(T) =vC(NnCl+1rl)(l+1)

k nCrl (T) for all T Ckl+1nCrl;hence we have that vN(l+1)

Ckl+1 =CCll+1

k nCrl = v(NnClr)(l+1)

Ckl+1nCrl =CCll+1

k nCrl; and so expression above can be restated as:

X

i2Cql

i(N; v) X

i2Cql

i(NnCrl; v)

= Shq vCN(l+1)l+1 k

=CCll+1

k Shq vNCl+1(l+1) k

=CCll+1 k nCrl : Analogously,

X

i2Crl

i(N; v) X

i2Crl

i(NnCql; v)

= Shr vCN(l+1)l+1 k

=CCll+1 k

Shr vNCl+1(l+1) k

=CCll+1 k nCql : SinceSh satis…es -BIC (Proposition 3),

Shq vNCl+1(l+1) k

=Cl

Ckl+1 Shq vCN(l+1)l+1 k

=Cl

Ckl+1nCrl q

=

Shr vNCl+1(l+1) k

=CCll+1 k

Shr vCN(l+1)l+1 k

=CCll+1 k nCql

r

:

(10)

Moreover, by de…nition of ; q = Cql and r = Crl ; thus we obtain the result.

5 Characterization

In this Section we provide a characterization of the value using the property of Balanced Per Capita Contributions introduced in the previous section.

Theorem 7 An e¢cient value f over the set of games with level structure satis…es BPCC if and only if f = :

Proof. Let (N; v;C) 2LT U and suppose there exist two e¢cient values f1 and f2 satisfying BPCC. We will prove that fC1l

q(N; v) = fC2l

q(N; v) for all l 2 f0; :::; hg and Cql 2 Cl; where fCxl

q(N; v) := P

i2Cqlfix(N; v), x = 1;2.

This is enough to prove the result because the Cql are singletons for l = 0.

Note that by e¢ciency, X

Cql2Cl

fCxl

q(N; v) =v(N) for x= 1;2:

We will prove the result by induction on the level. Consider level h;

Ch =fNg:Sincef1andf2 are e¢cient, we have thatfN1(v) =fN2(v) =v(N):

Let us assume that the result holds for level k; k l; i:e:

fC1k

q(v) =fC2k q(v) for all Cqk 2 Ck with l k h:

Let Cql 2 Cl: Denote Ql 1 :=fCrl 1 2 Cl 1 :Crl 1 Cqlg:

We use an induction argument on the cardinal of Ql 1:

Assume that Ql 1 = 1; sayQl 1 =fCql 1g: Hence, Ql 1 =fCqlg and by induction hypothesis:

fC1l 1

q (v) =fC1l

q(v) =fC2l

q(v) =fC2l 1

q (v):

Assume that the result holds for Ql 1 = m 1: Now we prove that it holds for Ql 1 =m:

Suppose that Ql 1 =m;sayQl 1 =fC1l 1; :::; Cml 1g:LetM =f1; :::; mg:

(11)

Let Crl 1; Csl 1 2 Ql 1: By BPCC, fC1l 1

r (N; v) fC1l 1

r (NnCsl 1; v)

jCrl 1j = fC1l 1

s (N; v) fC1l 1

s (NnCrl 1; v)

jCsl 1j (1) and

fC2l 1

r (N; v) fC2l 1

r (NnCsl 1; v)

jCrl 1j = fC2l 1

s (N; v) fC2l 1

s (NnCrl 1; v)

jCsl 1j : (2) Moreover, by induction hypothesis on Ql 1 we have thatfC1l 1

r (NnCsl 1; v) = fC2l 1

r (NnCsl 1; v) and fC1l 1

s (NnCrl 1; v) =fC2l 1

s (NnCrl 1; v):

Taking into account these expressions and operating with (1) and (2), we have that

fC1l 1

r (N; v) fC2l 1 r (N; v)

jCrl 1j = fC1l 1

s (N; v) fC2l 1 s (N; v) jCsl 1j

and so,

fC1l 1

r (N; v) fC2l 1

r (N; v) = Crl 1 jCsl 1j

hfC1l 1

s (N; v) fC2l 1

s (N; v)i

: (3)

Applying the induction hypothesis on levels, we have that fC1l

q(N; v) = fC2l

q(N; v): That is, X

Cpl 12Ql 1

fC1l 1

p (N; v) = X

Cpl 12Ql 1

fC2l 1

p (N; v):

Therefore,

0 = X

Clp 12Ql 1

fC1l 1

p (N; v) X

Cpl 12Ql 1

fC2l 1

p (N; v) (4)

= fC1l 1

1 (N; v) +::::+fC1l 1

m (N; v) fC2l 1

1 (N; v) :::: fC2l 1 m (N; v)

= fC1l 1 1

(N; v) fC2l 1 1

(N; v) +::::+ fC1l 1

m (N; v) fC2l 1

m (N; v) :

(12)

Takings = 1 in equation (3), we deduce that

fC1l 1

r (N; v) fC2l 1

r (N; v) = Crl 1 C1l 1

h fC1l 1

1 (N; v) fC2l 1

1 (N; v)i

(5)

for all Crl 1 2 Ql 1nC1l 1:

Replacing these expressions in (4),

0 = fC1l 1 1

(N; v) fC2l 1 1

(N; v) + C2l 1 C1l 1

hfC1l 1 1

(N; v) fC2l 1 1

(N; v)i

+:::::::+ Cml 1 C1l 1

h fC1l 1

1 (N; v) fC2l 1

1 (N; v)i

= fC1l 1

1 (N; v) fC2l 1

1 (N; v) C1l 1 + C2l 1 +::::+ Cml 1

C1l 1 :

But by de…nition,

C1l 1 + C2l 1 +::::+ Cml 1 C1l 1 >0;

therefore, fC1l 1 1

(N; v) fC2l 1 1

(N; v) = 0 and so,

fC1l 1

1 (N; v) =fC2l 1

1 (N; v):

Replacing this expression in (5) we conclude that

fC1l 1

r (N; v) =fC2l 1 r (N; v) for all Crl 1 2 Ql 1:

Using the same induction argument for any level t with 0 t l 1 we obtain that f1 =f2:

6 Concluding remarks

As opposed to Calvo et al. (1996), who characterized the LSV using the property of Balanced Group Contributions, we provide a characterization of

(13)

a new value using its per capita version. The advantage of these charac- terizations is that they do not use properties of additivity nor consistency.

Hence, the characterization results still hold for many relevant subfamilies of TU games, such as the family of simple games, totally balanced games, or games with a single coalition structure. In this latter case, the property of balanced per capita contributions reduces to two conditions: one of them is the property of Balanced Individual Contributions for the members of the same Coalition (BICC); formally

fi(N; v) fi(Nn fjg; v) =fj(N; v) fj(Nn fig; v)

for alli; jthat belong to the same coalitionCq. Following Calvo et al. (1996), the Owen value is the only e¢cient value that satis…es this property and Balanced Individual Contributions in the game between coalitions, formally

X

i2Cq

fi(N; v) X

i2Cq

fi(NnCr; v) = X

i2Cr

fi(N; v) X

i2Cr

fi(NnCq; v)

for all distinct coalitions Cq; Cr.

As opposed, is the only e¢cient value satisfying BICC and balanced per capita contributions among coalitions, formally

P

i2Cqfi(N; v) P

i2Cqfi(NnCr; v)

jCqj =

P

i2Crfi(N; v) P

i2Crfi(NnCq; v) jCrj

for all distinct coalitions Cq; Cr.

References

[1] Aumann, R. and Drèze, J. (1974)Cooperative games with coalition struc- ture. International Journal of Game Theory 3, 217–237.

[2] Calvo, E., Lasaga, J. and Winter, E. (1996) The principle of balanced contributions and hierarchies of cooperation. Mathematical Social Sci- ences 31, 171-182.

[3] Calvo, E. and Santos, J.C. (2000) Weighted weak semivalues. Interna- tional Journal of Game Theory 29, 1-9.

(14)

[4] Hamiache G. (2006) A value for games with coalition structures. Social Choice and Welfare 26, 93-105.

[5] Hart, S. and Kurz, M. (1983)Endogenous formation of coalitions. Econo- metrica 51 (4), 1047 1064.

[6] Hart, S. and Mas-Colell, A. (1989) Potencial, value and consistency.

Econometrica 57 (3), 589-614.

[7] Herings, P.J.J., van der Laan, G. and Talman, D. The component fair- ness solution for cycle-free graph games.CentER Discussion paper 2005- 127.

[8] Kalai, E., and Samet, D. (1987) On weighted Shapley values. Interna- tional Journal of Game Theory, 16, 205-222.

[9] Kalai, E., and Samet, D. (1988) Weighted Shapley values. In: A. Roth, ed., The Shapley value: Essays in honor of L. Shapley (Cambrige), Cam- brige University Press, 83-99.

[10] Kamijo Y. (2007) A collective value: a new interpretation of a value and a coalition structure. Waseda University. 21 COE-GLOPE Working Paper Series 27.

[11] Levy, A. and McLean, R.P. (1989) Weighted coalition structure values.

Games and Economic Behavior 1, 234-249.

[12] Myerson, R.B. (1980) Conference structures and fair allocation rules.

International Journal of Game Theory 9, 169-182.

[13] Owen, G. (1977) Values of games with a priori unions. In: Henn, R., Moeschlin, O. (eds.) Essays in mathematical economics and game theory (Berlin) Heidelberg NewYork: Springer, 76-88.

[14] Pérez-Castrillo, D. and Wettstein, D. (2001) Bidding for the surplus:

A non-cooperative approach to the Shapley value. Journal of Economic Theory 100, 274-294.

[15] Sánchez, F. (1997) Balanced contributions axiom in the solution of co- operative games. Games and Economic Behavior 20, 161-168.

(15)

[16] Shapley, L. S. (1953a) Additive and Non-Additive Set Functions.Ph.D.

Dissertation, Princeton University.

[17] Shapley, L. S. (1953b) A value for n-person games. In: Huhn, H.W.,Tucker, A.W. (eds.) Contributions to the theory of games II. An- nals of Mathematics Studies 28, pp. 307–317. Princeton: Princeton Uni- versity Press.

[18] Vidal-Puga, J. J. (2005) Implementation of the levels structure value.

Annals of Operations Research 137(1), 191-209.

[19] Vidal-Puga, J. J. (2006)The Harsanyi paradox and the "right to talk" in bargaining among coalitions.EconWPA Working paper number 0501005.

Available at http://ideas.repec.org/p/wpa/wuwpga/0501005.html.

[20] Winter, E. (1989) A value for cooperative games with level structure of cooperation. International Journal of Game Theory 18, 227-240.

Referenzen

ÄHNLICHE DOKUMENTE

Econometric studies of the substitutability of energy and other factors of production, based on international cross-section data, generally presuppose that energy is

To sum up, there is overall agreement that given the right institutions, more (quantity) and better (quality) education is good for economic growth, but there is clearly a lack

Then files may be copied one at a time (or with a wild card transfer) to the dual density diskette.. Using the Filer under the UCSD O/S, do an E)xtended listing of the files on

Given the analysis in Section 2 that suggested there was little evidence of convergence in emission per capita rates, this section examined the evidence for convergence in three

neoclassical model such as Solow-Swan model and the Ramsay model imply that a high rate of saving is conducive to economic growth.. While it is true that some East Asian

On February 26, 2016, the Finnish government announced that as of September 1, 2016, approximately 50 additional personnel would be deployed in support of existing training

It can be seen as a warning for the VET sector as well as for that type of education in the coming years, especially when it comes to the overlap with the EHEA in the

As noted above, a catch up process involving differential productivity growth affects the dynamics of the real exchange rate in the catching up economy (the Balassa- Samuelson