• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

Forcing: How to prove unprovability The Continuum Hypothesis Regula Krapf

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Aktie "Forcing: How to prove unprovability The Continuum Hypothesis Regula Krapf"

Copied!
28
0
0

Wird geladen.... (Jetzt Volltext ansehen)

Volltext

(1)

Forcing: How to prove unprovability

The Continuum Hypothesis

Regula Krapf

University of Koblenz-Landau, Campus Koblenz

June 26, 2018

(2)

Content

1 The technique of forcing

2 Cohen forcing

3 Lebesgue measure

4 Forcing¬CH

(3)

Motivation

Theorem (Cantor)

There is no surjection from Nonto P(N).

This lead to the study ofinfinite cardinals.

Definition

0 denotes the cardinality ofω =N. ℵ1 denotes the least uncountable cardinal.

2 denotes the second-least uncountable cardinal.

c=20 denotes the cardinality of P(ω).

(4)

The Continuum Hypothesis

In 1878, Georg Cantor conjectured the Continuum Hypothesis:

Conjecture (The Continuum Hypothesis (CH))

There is no cardinal between ℵ0 and20, i.e. 20 =ℵ1.

The Continuum Hypothesis was the first of Hilbert’s famous list of 23 open Problems.

In 1940, Kurt Gödel constructed a model of ZFC (denoted L) in which the Continuum Hypothesis holds.

In 1963, Paul Cohen proved that CH is actually independent of the axioms of ZFC, i.e. both ZFC+CH and ZFC+¬CH are consistent.

The method he used (and developed for this result) isforcing.

(5)

Forcing notions

Definition

A forcing (notion) is a non-atomic partial order P= (P,≤P,1P) with a maximal element 1P, i.e.

P is reflexive, transitive and antisymmetric, for every p ∈P,p≤P 1P,

for every p ∈Pthere are p0,p1P p which are incompatible, i.e.

there is nor ∈P withr ≤P p0,p1.

(6)

Forcing notions

Example (Cohen forcing)

Let P=Fn(ω,2,ℵ0) be the set of partial functionsp:dom(p)→2 with dom(p)⊆ω finite, ordered by reverse inclusion, i.e.

p ≤P q ⇐⇒dom(p)⊇dom(q) andpdom(q) =q. Furthermore, let 1P=∅, the empty function.

(7)

Generic filters

Definition

LetM be a countable transitive model of ZFC andPM be a forcing notion.

1 A subsetDPis said to bedense, if for everypP there is someqP p withqD.

2 A subsetG Pis said to be aP-generic filter, if it has the following properties:

IfpPqandpG, thenqG.

Ifp,qG then there isr G such thatr Pp,q.

IfDPis a dense set which is inM, thenGD6=∅.

Example

Consider Cohen forcingP=Fn(ω,2,0). Then for eachnω, the set Dn={pP|ndom(p)}is dense.

(8)

Names

Definition

Let Pbe a forcing notion. A P-name is a set whose elements are of the form (σ,p), where σ is a P-name andp∈P.

This definition requires transfinite recursion.

Example

LetM |=ZFC and PM a forcing notion.

is aP-name.

Letx M. Then there is acanonicalP-name forx given by

ˇx={(ˇy,1P)|yx}.

The setG˙ ={(ˇp,p)|pP}is aP-name, the canonicalP-name for a P-generic filter.

(9)

Evaluations of names

Let Pbe a forcing notion and G aP-generic filter. We can evaluate a P-nameσ as follows:

σG ={τG | ∃p ∈G : (τ,p)∈σ}.

Example

G =∅.

Letx ∈M. Then ˇ

xG ={ˇyG |y ∈x}={y |y ∈x}=x by transfinite induction.

G ={ˇpG |p∈G}=G.

(10)

Generic extensions

Let M |=ZFC,P∈M be a non-trivial forcing notion andG aP-generic filter. Then we define

M[G] ={σG |σ is a P-name}.

Fact

1 M∪ {G} ⊆M[G]

2 G ∈/ M.

3 M[G]|=ZFC.

Proof.

For (2) suppose that G ∈M. Then the set D =P\G is inM. Moreover, D is dense: Letp∈P. Since Pis non-atomic, there arep0,p1P p such that p0 andp1 are incompatible. But then at least one of p0,p1 is not in G.

(11)

Where do generic filters live?

Suppose that V|=ZFC and V contains countable, transitive modelsM ∈V of ZFC. Let P∈M be a forcing notion. We extend M to M[G], whereG is a P-generic filter contained in V.

Fact

For every p ∈Pthere is a P-generic filter G in Vwith p∈G .

Proof.

SinceM is countable, M contains only countably many dense subsets ofP. Let (Dn|n∈ω) enumerate them (in V). Now we inductively construct a sequence of conditions (pn|n∈ω)by

p0 =p

Givenpn, letpn+1Ppn withpn+1 ∈Dn.

Then G ={q∈P| ∃n ∈ω:pnPq} is a P-generic filter overM.

(12)

The idea behind names

Every element of M[G]has aP-nameσ∈M butM does not know howσ will be evaluated. This is similar to the case of extensions of fields:

Consider Qand an algebraic closureQ¯ of Q.

InQ, the polynomialX2−2 names the root √ 2∈Q¯. If we extendQto Q[√

2], then√

2 is the evaluation ofX2−2.

(13)

Cohen forcing

LetP denoteFn(ω,2,0)and letG beP-generic overM. InM[G], consider the function

c= [

p∈G

p. (c is called aCohen real)

Fact

1 c is a functionω2.

2 If f M is a function f :ω2then f 6=c.

Proof.

(1)

Letnω. If there are p,qG such thatndom(p)dom(q)and p(n)6=q(n), thenp andq are incompatible.

To see that dom(c) =ω, note thatDn={pP|ndom(p)}is dense.

LetpGDn. Thenndom(c)andc(n) =p(n).

(14)

Cohen forcing

LetP denoteFn(ω,2,0)and letG beP-generic overM. InM[G], consider the function

c= [

p∈G

p. (c is called aCohen real)

Fact

1 c is a functionω2.

2 If f M is a function f :ω2then f 6=c.

Proof.

(2) ConsiderDf ={pP| ∃ndom(p) :p(n)6=f(n)}. We claim thatDf is a dense subset of P. LetpP. Since dom(p)is finite, there isnω\dom(p).

Then q=p∪ {(n,1f(n))} ≤Pp andqDf.

Takep0GDf and letn0dom(p0)such thatp0(n0)6=f(n0). Then c(n0) =p0(n0)and soc6=f.

(15)

A nice application: Cantor’s Theorem

Theorem (Cantor)

There is no surjection from ω onto P(ω).

Proof.

Suppose the contrary. Observe that P=Fn(ω,2,ℵ0)is countable. Then so is P(P), so we can enumerate (in M) all dense subsets of P. But then we can construct in M aP-generic filter over M.

(16)

The Cantor space

We identify Rwith ω2, the space of functions ω→2.

Observation

If P is a forcing notion andG isP-generic overM, thenRM andRM[G] do not have to be the same.

(17)

Intervals in the Cantor space

We define intervals in the following way: For

s ∈2={t :dom(t)→2|dom(t)∈ω} we define Is ={x ∈R|s ⊆x} ⊆R and we define µ(Is) =2−dom(s).

Definition

We say that a set X ⊆Rhas measure zero, if for every ε >0 there exists a sequence (In|n∈ω) of intervals in Rsuch that X ⊆S

n∈ωIn and P

n∈ωµ(Is)< ε.

(18)

Theorem

Let M[G]be a generic extension of M by Cohen forcing, and let c ∈M[G] be the canonical Cohen real. Then in M[G],RM has measure zero.

Proof.

Let ε >0, let k∈ω such that ε >2−k. For n∈ω define sn:k+n+1→2,sn(l) =c(n+l).

Now define In=Isn. Then X

n∈ω

µ(In) =X

n∈ω

2−(k+n+1) =2−k < ε.

(19)

Proof, continued.

sn:k+n+1→2,sn(l) =c(n+l),In=Isn. It remains to check: RM ⊆S

n∈ωIn.Let x ∈RM. Then

Dx ={p∈P|∃n∈ω∀l <k+n+1:n+l ∈dom(p)

∧p(n+l) =x(l)} ∈M

is a dense subset of Cohen forcing P. Takep ∈G ∩Dx andn∈ω which witnesses thatp ∈Dx. Then

∀l <k+n+1:sn(l) =c(n+l) =p(n+l) =x(l) and so sn⊆x andx ∈In.

(20)

Forcing ¬CH

We have used Cohen forcing to add one real c which is not an element of the ground modelM. What happens if we addℵ2-many Cohen reals in this way?

Definition

Let Fn(ℵM2 ×ω,2,ℵ0)denote the set of finite partial functions from ℵM2 ×ω→2, ordered by reverse inclusion.

(21)

Forcing ¬CH

Let Pdenote Fn(ℵM2 ×ω,2,ℵ0)and let G beP-generic over M.

Lemma

The following statements hold:

1 F =S

p∈Gp is a function F :ℵM2 ×ω →2.

2 For each α <ℵM2 , let cα(n) =F(α,n). Then for all α < β <ℵM2 , cα 6=cβ.

Proof.

(1) Follows from the density of the sets

Dα,n={p ∈P|(α,n)∈dom(p)}

for all α <ℵM2 andn ∈ω.

(22)

Forcing ¬CH

Let Pdenote Fn(ℵM2 ×ω,2,ℵ0)and let G beP-generic over M.

Lemma

The following statements hold:

1 F =S

p∈Gp is a function F :ℵM2 ×ω →2.

2 For α <ℵM2 , let cα(n) =F(α,n). Then for all α < β <ℵM2 , cα6=cβ. Proof.

(2) For all α < β <ℵM2 consider

Dαβ ={p∈P| ∃n ∈ω : (α,n),(β,n)∈dom(p)andp(α,n)6=p(β,n)}.

Then Dαβ is dense in P. By genericity, takep∈G ∩Dαβ andn∈ω such that (α,n),(β,n)∈dom(p)with p(α,n)6=p(β,n). Then

cα(n) =F(α,n) =p(α,n)6=p(β,n) =F(β,n) =cβ(n).

(23)

Forcing ¬CH

The previous lemma shows that there are at leastℵM2 many reals inM[G], so if we can show thatℵM2 =ℵM[G2 ] then inM[G]

(20)M[G]=|RM[G]| ≥ ℵM2 =ℵM[G2 ].

Definition

Let Pbe a forcing notion.

1 An antichain inP is a subsetA⊆Pwith the property that all

elements of Aare incompatible, i.e. for allp,q ∈A, there is nor ∈P with r≤P p,q.

2 P satisfies thecountable chain condition (ccc), if every antichain inP is at most countable.

(24)

Forcing ¬CH

Theorem

If Psatisfies the ccc then Ppreserves all cardinals, i.e. |κ|M[G]=κin every P-generic extension M[G]. In particular,ℵM[G2 ]=ℵM2 .

How can it happen thatℵM2 is collapsed?

(25)

Forcing ¬CH

Theorem

If Psatisfies the ccc then Ppreserves all cardinals, i.e. |κ|M[G]=κin every P-generic extension M[G]. In particular,ℵM[G2 ]=ℵM2 .

Example

Consider the forcing notion

Col(ω,ℵM2 ) ={p:dom(p)→ ℵM2 |dom(p)⊆ω finite}

ordered by reverse inclusion. If G is Col(ω,ℵM2 )-generic, thenF =S

p∈G p is a function ω→ ℵM2 . ThenF is surjective because for eachα <ℵM2 the set

Dα={p ∈Col(ω,ℵM2 )| ∃n∈dom(p) :p(n) =α}

is dense. So in M[G]we have ℵM2 =ℵM[G0 ].

(26)

Forcing ¬CH

Lemma

P=Fn(ℵM2 ×ω,2,ℵ0) has the ccc.

Proof.

Suppose that (pi |i <ℵM1 )enumerates an uncountable antichain. Then there is a setX ⊆ ℵM1 of size ℵM1 andn∈ω such that

∀i ∈X : |dom(pi)|=n.

Now letm≤n be maximal such that there is a set b with |b|=m and Y ⊆X of sizeℵM1 such that for alli ∈Y,b⊆dom(pi).

We claim that for all x ∈/ b there isi(x)<ℵM1 such that for all i >i(x)in Y,x ∈/ dom(pi). This holds because otherwiseb∪ {x}would contradict the maximality ofm.

(27)

Forcing ¬CH

Proof, continued.

Y ⊆ ℵ1 of sizeℵM1 withb⊆dom(pi) for alli ∈Y.

for all x ∈/ b,i(x)<ℵM1 with x ∈/ dom(pi) for alli >i(x) in Y. We construct an increasing sequence (iξ|ξ <ℵ1) withiξ∈Y by recursion:

Suppose that (iξ |ξ < ζ) has already been defined. Then letiζ be the minimal ordinal i ∈Y such that

i >sup{i(x)| ∃ξ < ζ :x ∈dom(pξ)}.

Now letξ < ζ <ℵM1 . We claim that dom(piξ)∩dom(piζ)⊆b. Let x ∈dom(piξ)∩dom(piζ) andx ∈/ b. Theniζ>i(x) and so x ∈/ dom(piζ).

But there are only countably many possibilities for piξ b, so there must be some ξ 6=ζ such that piξ andpiζ are compatible.

(28)

Forcing ¬CH

Thus we have proved Theorem (Gödel,Cohen)

CH is independent of the axioms ofZFC.

Thank you for your attention!

Referenzen

ÄHNLICHE DOKUMENTE

Figure 5: Statistical power and FDR versus proba- bility of non-null hypotheses π 1 for naively composed Storey-BH (at batch sizes 10, 100, and 1000).. Figure 4 and Fig- ure 5 show

Рис. Комплекс моделей предметно - технологического проектирования.. 18 демонстрирует разработанный метод двухуровневого моделирования производственной линии,

Based on results of research we can recommend the following rules of trading on short-term market overreactions: 1 detection of anomaly abnormal return – as a criterion can

☛ A la suite de ces r´esultats, les mod`eles de croissance ´economique de long terme des pays analys´es sont estim´es. Ils montrent que le taux de croissance ´economique, est

Tax Design in the OECD: A test of the Hines-Summers Hypothesis. Furceri, Davide and

We focus on the changes in regional inequality in the second matured growth period, looking at three different regions of Korea; Seoul, metropolitan cities and

the FO-theory ZFC implies that every ‘internal model of Peano’s axioms’ is isomorphic to ‘the internal realisation of the natural numbers on

Avec Federal Power Commission v. Hope Natural Gas Co. 20 le droit de règlementer le taux de profit est maintenant délégué aux commissions de règlementation.