• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

Progressive Taxation and the Equal Sacrifice Principle

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Aktie "Progressive Taxation and the Equal Sacrifice Principle"

Copied!
15
0
0

Wird geladen.... (Jetzt Volltext ansehen)

Volltext

(1)

NOT FOR QUOTATION WITHOUT THE PERMISSION OF THE AUTHOR

Progressive Taxatipn and the Equal Sacrifice Principle

HP. Young

June 1986 CP-86-18

Collaborative P a p e r s r e p o r t work which has not been performed solely at t h e International Institute f o r Applied Systems Analysis and which h a s received only limited review. Views or opinions expressed herein do not necessarily represent those of t h e Institute, its National Member Organizations, or o t h e r organizations supporting the work.

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR APPLIED SYSTEMS ANALYSIS 2361 Laxenburg, Austria

(2)
(3)

Foreword

A traditional justification f o r progressive taxation is that it imposes equal sa- crifice on all taxpayers in loss of utility. Nevertheless, many plausible utility functions yield strictly regressive taxes when all taxpayers sacrifice equally. If tax rates are required t o be progressive, nonnegative, and independent of scale, then t h e r e is a unique family of positive, increasing, continuous utility functions that is consistent with equal rate of sacrifice. They determine a unique family of tax schedules that seem not to have been studied before except in isolated cases.

Alexander B. Kurzhanski Chairman

System and Decision Sciences Program

-

iii

-

(4)
(5)

Progressive

Taxation

and t@e Equal Sacrifice Principle

HP. Young

School of Public Affairs University of Maryland College P a r k , Md. 20742

1. Introduction

'? have not been able t o discover who w a s t h e first t o proclaim t h e thesis that because t h e degree of utility of income decreases when income increases, it follows that equality of sacrifice entails progressive taxation". ([2], p. 48). So begins a learned paper by A.J. Cohen Stuart (1889) on t h e utilitarian foundations of pro- gressive taxation. Cohen Stuart points out that 'equal sacrifice' may be interpret- ed in two ways. Equal absolute sacrifice means that in paying taxes everyone gives up t h e same amount of utility relative t o his initial position. Equal r a t e of sa- crifice means that everyone gives up the s a m e percentage in utility. Assuming t h a t t h e marginal utility of income f a l l s as income rises, it is clear that the r i c h e r must pay more in tax than the poorer if all are t o sacrifice equally by either criterion.

It is not s o clear, however, that the r i c h e r must pay a higher percentage of their incomes in taxes t o achieve equality of sacrifice. In fact, f o r many plausible utili- t y functions this is not t h e case. By itself, then, t h e equal sacrifice doctrine does not imply progressive taxation.

Instead of attempting to justify progressive taxes by equal sacrifice, w e may turn t h e argument around: if a progressive (or flat) tax is deemed t o be the ap- propriate outcome of an equal sacrifice model, what implications does this have f o r t h e form of the utility function? More generally, might it be possible to deduae pertinent infomation about t h e utility function by examining t h e properties of the tax schedules that result from t h e equal sacrifice principle? The answer is affir- mative. We shall show t h a t t h r e e simple properties of the tax system-

*

This work was supported by the National Science Foundation under Grant SES-8319530 a t the University of Maryland.

(6)

nonnegativity, progressivity, and scale-invariance-are enough to completely determine t h e form of t h e utility functions, whether equal absolute o r equal rate of sacrifice is t h e criterion. In both cases, the implied family of tax schedules is t h e same.

The study of formal properties of tax schedules h a s a long and distinguished tradition going back t o t h e work of Cohen S t u a r t [2], Edgeworth [3]. and o t h e r s around t h e t u r n of t h e last century. This axiomatic point of view has recently been revived in t h e work of W.F. Richter [9],

[lo],

Eichhorn and Funke [4], Eichhorn, Funke and Richter [5], and Pfaehler [?I, among others. It differs substantially from t h e optimal tax l i t e r a t u r e (e.g., Mirrlees [ 6 ] ) in t h a t tax systems a r e derived from elementary principles of equity and consistency, r a t h e r than from c r i t e r i a of economic optimality

.

2. The equal sncrifice principle

Let z r e p r e s e n t an individual's taxable income, and u (z) t h e utility of income level z. For purposes of this discussion, every individual is assumed t o have t h e s a m e utility function f o r income. W e make t h e following regularity assumptions:

u (z) is defined f o r all z

>

0. u (z) may o r may not be bounded above o r below.

A t a z schedule is a function t = J (z) defined f o r all z

>

0, where t i s t h e tax paid on income z and 0 S J (z )

<

z

.

That is, taxes are nonnegative and nonconfis- catory. J is progressive if, f o r all z , J (z ) / z is monotone nondecreasing in z

.

J is s t r i c t l y progressive if J (z) / z is strictly monotone increasing in z

.

Thus t h e flat tax P(z) = rz where 0 S r

< 11

is progressive but not strictly so.

Say t h a t J (z) i n d u c e s equal sactipice if

J (z ) i n d u c e s an equal r a t e of sactipice if

Note that, since 0 S J (z)

<

z and u (z) i s strictly increasing, w e must have c 2 0 in (1). Moreover, c

>

0 unless J(z) is identically zero. For (2) t o be well- defined, u (z ) # 0, and hence by continuity either u (z )

>

0 f o r all z

>

0, o r u(z)

<

0 f o r all z

>

0. The former case is the more natural, and implies t h a t 0 S r

<

1 i n (2).

(7)

O u r goal is to gain more information about t h e form of t h e utility functions in (1) and (2) by studying t h e p r o p e r t i e s of t h e tax schedules t h a t they engender. W e have already required t h a t t a x e s b e nonnegative, i.e., t h a t t h e r e b e no minimum in- come guarantee o r o t h e r form of d i r e c t subsidization through t h e tax system. This , is a significant assumption, but accords with much c u r r e n t practice. Second, i t seems intuitively reasonable t h a t a tax schedule which metes o u t equal sacrifice will be e i t h e r progressive o r flat, but not strictly regressive. In o t h e r words, if a proposed measure of utility yields nonprogressive taxation, t h e n w e may suspect t h a t it a t t r i b u t e s too g r e a t a marginal value of income to t h e rich.

Third, i t seems reasonable t h a t tax r a t e s should depend only on t h e relative distribution of incomes, not on t h e absolute monetary units in which incomes are measured. In o t h e r words, if incomes all increase by a fixed percentage, so t h a t t h e relative distribution of incomes remains unchanged, and if t h e total tax burden increases by t h e same percentage, then t h e relative distribution of taxes should remain unchanged. Such a tax system is s c a l e i n u a t i a n t . Scale-invariance can be interpreted as a simple principle of distributive equity: if taxes a n d incomes all increase or d e c r e a s e in some fixed proportion, then equity i s preserved. I t can also b e r e g a r d e d as merely a pragmatic principle t h a t allows t h e tax system t o b e re-indexed without changing t h e relative distribution of t h e tax burden.

3. Utility functions and tax myatema consintent with absolute equality of - d i c e

Let f ( z ) b e a tax schedule t h a t induces equal absolute sacrifice under t h e utility function u (z). Thus f and u satisfy (I), o r equivalently

Note t h a t t h e inverse of u exists because u i s assumed to b e strictly increas- ing. Expression (3) shows t h a t f can b e regarded as a function of two variables:

t h e income level z and t h e amount of sacrifice c . As c varies, f ( z , c ) defines a family of tax schedules t h a t allows different amounts of tax to be raised relative to any fixed distribution of incomes. f ( z , c ) is called a parametric t a z schedule.

Parametric families c r o p up in a wide variety of f a i r division problems

[Ill.

Scale-invariance of t h e tax system based on f ( z , c ) amounts t o saying t h a t , f o r e v e r y scale f a c t o r A

>

0, and f o r e v e r y constant c Z 0 , t h e r e exists a constant c' (depending on A) such t h a t

(8)

In o t h e r words, t h e t a x schedule c a n b e r e - i n d e r a d by changing c t o c', and t h e proportion of t a x paid to income received will remain fixed f o r a l l persons.

If j imposes absolute s a c r i f i c e and i s scale-invariant t h e n s e v e r a l important p r o p e r t i e s of t h e utility function may b e deduced. In p a r t i c u l a r , differences in utility levels will b e p r e s e r v e d (in an ordinal sense) under a uniform change of scale. Consider two individuals, one with initial income r and a f t e r - t a x income y , 0

<

y S r , and a n o t h e r with initial income r ' and a f t e r tax income y ', 0

<

y ' S r

'.

Equal absolute s a c r i f i c e implies t h a t u ( 2 )

-

u ( y ) = u (2')

-

u ( y ') = c 2 0. By

definition of J , y = r

-

j ( r , c ) and y ' = r ' - j ( r ' , c ) . Since j i s scale-invariant, f o r e v e r y A

>

0 t h e r e i s a c ' 2 0 such t h a t

Ay

=

Xz - j ( X z , c f ) and Ay'

=

Xz' - j ( X z ' , c f )

.

Hence by (3)

That is, f o r e v e r y z , r ', y , y '

>

0 and e v e r y A

>

0 ,

Such a function u is said to b e homogeneous i n d m r e n c e s .

Lemma. If u ( r ) is continuous, nondecreasing, and homogeneous in differences, t h e n u ( r ) i s of form

(i) u ( r ) = b , o r

(ii) u ( z ) = a . Z n z + b , a > O , o r (iii) u ( z ) = a z P + b , ap > O

.

(9)

Proof.* If u (z ) is homogeneous in differences, then t h e r e is a single-valued func- tion F such that f o r all 0

<

y r z and all X

>

0,

Since u is continuous, F is too. Let D = [ u ( z ) -u(y):O

<

y r z j . By con- tinuity, D is an interval of R + of form [O,m ) o r [O,m ], where m

>

0 unless u (z ) is constant, which is case (i) of t h e lemma. Suppose then that m

>

0. If z ,z' 2 0 and z + z ' < m , then z + z t = u ( z ) - u ( y ) f o r some z and y . Since 0 S z S u ( z ) - u ( y ) , wehave

Thus by t h e continuity of u ( z ) t h e r e exists some w between z and y such that u ( w ) = u ( z ) - 2 ; t h a t is z = u ( z ) - u ( w ) . Hence also z '

=

u ( w ) - u ( y ) . This argument shows t h a t f o r every X

>

0,

F(z +z',A)=F(z,X)+F(z',X) provided z , z ' 2 O and z + z t < m

.

(6) Since F is continuous, F may be continuously extended s o t h a t (6) also holds when- e v e r z ,z' r 0 and z

+

z ' = m . It follows from [I] (Section 2.1.4, Theorem 3) that

F(z,X) = c(X)z f o r all 0 S z S m , all X > O

.

Since u is nondecreasing,

u ( & )

-

u(Xy)

=

c(X)[u(z)

-

u ( y ) I f o r all =,'I/

>

0

.

Fix y*

>

0, and let d(X)

=

u (Ay*)

-

c(X)u (y*). Then

u ( & ) = c(A)u(z)

+

d(X) f o r all z,X

>

0.

.-

For all real numbers r define u * ( r ) = u ( e f ) , c*(r) = c ( e f ) , and d * ( r ) = d ( e f ) . Making t h e substitutions s = In X and t

=

In z , t h e preceding becomes

By [I] (Section 3.1.3, Theorem 1) this, together with t h e continuity and monotonici- ty of u* , implies t h a t

*The proof o f t h i s r e s u l t originated in collaboration w i t h Janos Aceel during s pleasant d r i v e t o - g e t h e r a c r o s s southern Germany in July, 1985. His contribution and helpful comments on t h e manuscript a r e g r a t e f u l l y acknowledged.

(10)

Therefore.

I t should b e remarked t h a t , if u ( z ) is assumed t o be continuous, homogeneous in differences, and n o n c o n s t a n t (instead of nondecreasing), then t h e above argu- ment shows t h a t u must b e of form (i) o r (ii) with a # 0, o r (iii) with ap f 0.

Theorem. Let t h e utility of income u ( z ) b e continuous and strictly increasing f o r all incomes z

>

0, and let f ( z ,c ) be a scale-invariant, progressive family of tax schedules t h a t induces a n equal level of sacrifice c 2 0 f o r all positive income lev- els. Then f o r some fixed a , p

>

0 and all z

>

0,

f ( z r c ) = ( l - e - I a ) z and u ( z ) = a Lnz + b , a >O; (0

f ( 2 . c )

=

z

-

Z a n d u ( z ) = - c z z * + b , a , p > O

.

(ii) [I +;ZP / a ll/P

Proof: By t h e lemma, u ( z ) must b e of t h e form aln z

+

b f o r some a

>

0 o r a x P

+

b f o r ap

>

0. The case of constant u ( z ) i s ruled out since it is assumed h e r e t h a t u ( z ) i s s t r i c t l y increasing. f ( z ) yields a constant level of sacrifice c

r

0 if and only if

If u ( z ) = aln a

+

b , (7) implies t h a t

(11)

which is case (i) of the theorem. If u ( z )

=

a z P

+

b w e have two possibilities:

C-1: u ( z ) = a z P + b , a > O , p > O

.

Then u - l ( y ) = [ ( y - b ) / a l i / p , and ( 7 ) becomes f ( z , c ) = z - [ z P - c / a l l / P . This i s not progressive f o r c > 0 , since f ( z , c ) / z = 1 - [ 1

-

c / z P a ] l / P is strictly decreasing in z .

Came2: U ( Z ) = a z P + b , a < O , p < O .

Replace a by -a and p by p and write u ( z ) = --azv

+

b , where a

>

0,

p

>

0, and b i s unrestricted. Then u - l ( y ) = [ a / ( b

-

y ) l l / p and ( 7 ) becomes

These schedules are progressive f o r all c 2 0, and strictly s o f o r c

>

0. 0

S e t a = I and f o r every p > O define f p ( z , c ) = z - z / ( l + C Z P ) ~ / P . Also, define f o ( ~ ,C ) = ( 1

-

e * ) z f o r all z

>

0. These tax schedules form a single fami- ly with two parameters: p essentially determines t h e progressivity of t h e schedule and f o r each fixed p , c determines t h e amount of tax t o be levied.

4. Utility fundions and tax systems consistent with an equal rate of acrif ice

Consider now a utility function that induces an equal r a t e of sacrifice over all income levels. For this notion t o be well-defined, w e must have u ( z ) # 0 f o r all

z

>

0. That is, t h e utility of income must be everywhere positive o r everywhere

negative. The more natural case is t h e former, and t h e r e is no r e a l loss of gen- erality in assuming it, f o r if u ( z ) is negative, increasing, and an equal rate of sa- crifice regime prevails, then i t also prevails under I / lu ( z ) l , which i s positive and increasing.

Let u ( 2 ) be positive, continuous, and strictly increasing, and let f (2) induce a c o n s h n t rate of sacrifice r , 0 r r

<

1 . By definition,

u ( z -f ( 2 ) )

1

-

= r f o r a l l z > O

.

24 ( 2 ) Thus

(12)

Therefore t h e arguments of t h e preceding section apply, since f' ( z ) induces equal absolute sacrifice relative t o t h e transformed utility function In u ( 2 ) . I t follows t h a t t h e only progressive and scale-invariant tax schedules t h a t are consistent with an equal rate of sacrifice are essentially t h e same as those t h a t are con- sistent with equal absolute sacrifice. The difference between t h e two cases is t h e required form of the utility function. There are two possibilities. One is t h a t In u ( z ) = a In z + b , a >0, in which case U ( Z ) = @ z a where a > O and B = e b

>

0. Then an equal rate of sacrifice at rate r results from imposing t h e flat tax t = y ( z , r )

=

[ I

-

( l - r ) l / a ] z . \

The second possibility is t h a t In u ( z )

=

--az

+

6 , where a , p

>

0. Then u ( z ) is of t h e form

An equal rate of sacrifice at r a t e t = f ' ( z , r ) = z

-

- z / ( l - [ I n ( l - r ) ] z P / l / P . r results from imposing t h e t a x These results a r e summarized below.

Corollary. Let utility of income u ( z ) be positive, continuous, and strictly in- creasing f o r all incomes z

>

0, and let

y(z

, r ) b e a scale-invariant, progressive family of tax schedules t h a t induces a n equal rate of sacrifice 0 S r

<

1 on all po- sitive incomes. Then

z )= [ I - - r a z and u ( z ) = @ z a , a , 6 > O , ( 9

f ( z , r ) = z

-

Z and u ( z ) = @e-* , a , B. P

>

0

.

(ii)

[ 1 -[In (1 -r ) ] z P / a l l / P

Cohen S t u a r t , who originated t h e formal approach t o equal sacrifice in taxa- tion. advocated t h e use of a utility function of form u ( z )

=

aln z

+

b , a

>

0, to- g e t h e r with equal rate of sacrifice as t h e criterion. This gives r i s e t o tax schedules of t h e form

where r , 0 r r

<

1 is t h e rate of sacrifice. These functions are known as Cohen Stuart tazes. They were also mentioned as a possibility by Edgeworth, who pro-

(13)

posed t h a t they might b e a p p r o p r i a t e as a s u r h x yoked onto some o t h e r h x [3].

Let z* = e + l a , which may b e interpreted as t h e "minimum subsistence" level of income. Then Cohen Stuart's utility and h x functions may b e written as

U ( Z ) = aln(z/zL) and t = z - z * ( z / z * ) l 9 .

Cohen S t u a r t taxes do not satisfy t h e conditions of t h e foregoing theorem on several counts. First, t h e rate of sacrifice is undefined when z

=

x * , i.e., when t h e z e r o level of utility i s reached. Second, when z

<

z*, t a x e s become negative.

Third, and perhaps m o s t disturbing, t h e tax rates paid by individuals depend not only on t h e relative distribution of incomes in society, but also on t h e absolute lev- e l z* t h a t i s supposed to have z e r o utility. In o t h e r words, a p r e c i s e definition of what constitutes t h e subsistence level i s crucial to t h e validity of t h e scheme in equal sacrifice terms.

5. Conclusion

The equal sacrifice approach to progressive taxation is appealing in princi- ple. But i t i s far f r o m clear a pFiori what form t h e utility function should t a k e , or whether equal absolute or equal rate of sacrifice is t h e m o s t a p p r o p r i a t e cri- terion. One can gain insight into these questions by imposing elementary condi- tions on t h e tax functions t h a t a r i s e f r o m a n equal sacrifice model. A s w e have seen, equal sacrifice plus nonnegativity, progressivity, and scale-invariance is consistent with only a very special class of utility functions.

The f l a t tax implies equal absolute sacrifice if and only if utility is represent- ed by u (z ) = aln z

+

b for some a

>

0, and implies equal rate of sacrifice if and only if utility is represented by u (z) = @za, a , @

>

0. A s t r i c t l y progressive, nonnegative, and scale-invariant tax implies equal absolute sacrifice if and only if utility is r e p r e s e n t e d by u (z) = -ax*

+

b , where a , p

>

0. I t implies equal rate of sacrifice if and only if utility is represented by u ( z ) =bee', where a , b , p

>

0. The class -uz*

+

b i s bounded above and unbounded below, whereas t h e class be-' i s positive, bounded both above and below, and u ( z ) -, 0 as z -, 0. Since a positive utility of income to b e more sensible intuitively than one t h a t is unbounded below, i t a p p e a r s t h a t equal r a t e of sacrifice seems to b e t h e more natural criterion when w e examine both t h e form of t h e utility functions and of t h e tax schedules t h a t are consistent with it.

(14)

-

10

-

Finally, t h e r e is only one family of tax schedules t h a t is consistent with equal sacrifice u n d e r e i t h e r d e n i t i o n , and is nonnegative, progressive, and scale- invariant. This s a m e family has another desirable feature: namely, a tax can be levied in successive installments with t h e same outcome as if i t had been levied all at once [12].

Schedules of t h e above type can b e f i t quite closely to r e c e n t tax schedules in t h e U.S. and in West Germany [12]. This fact suggests t h a t one could use actual tax

d a t a to estimate t h e value of p in formula (ii) of t h e Theorem (or t h e Corollary).

For r e c e n t US and West German data, t h e estimated values of p are in t h e vicinity of .65 to .75. If one hypothesizes t h a t tax schedules to some d e g r e e reflect what a given society perceives to b e equal sacrifice, then such estimates might b e t r e a t e d in t u r n as estimates of t h e parameters in t h e utility functions themselves.

[I] Aczel, J. Lectures o n f i n c t i o n a l Equations a n d their Applications, N e w York, Academic P r e s s , 1966.

[2] Cohen S t u a r t , A.J. On progressive taxation, in R.A Musgrave and P.B.

Peacock (Eds.), Classics in the Theory o f h b l i c finance, New York: McGraw Hill, 1958.

[3] Edgeworth, F.Y. The p u r e theory of taxation, in R.A. Musgrave and P.B.

Peacock (Eds.), Classics in the Theory of h b l i c Ftnance. New York:

McGraw Hill, 1958.

[4] Eichhorn, W. and H. Funke, A c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n of the proportional income t a z , P r e p r i n t , University of Karlsruhe, West Germany, 1984.

[5] Eichhorn, W., Funke, H. and W.F. Richter, Tax progression and inequality of income distribution, Journal ofMathematical Economics 3 3 (1984), 127-131.

[6] Mirrlees, J.A. An exploration in t h e theory of optimum taxation, Review of Economic S t u d i e s 38 (1971), 175-208.

[7] Pfaehler, W. Normative Theorie d e r f i s k a l i s c h m Bestsuerung, Frankfurt, West Germany: P e t e r Lang Verlag, 1978.

[8] Pfingsten, A. The Measurement of Trrz Progression, Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Karlsruhe, West Germany, 1985.

(15)

[9] Richter, W.F. "A normative justification of progressive taxation: How to compromise on Nash and Kalai-Smorodinsky", in 0. Moeschlin and D. Pal- laschke (eds), Came m e o w a n d Mathematicad Economics, Amsterdam:

North-Holland Publishing Company, 1981.

[lo]

Richter, W.F. From ability t o pay t o concepts of equal sacrifice, Journad of Public Economics 20 (1983). 211-229.

[Ill

Young, H.P. "On dividing a n amount according t o individual claims o r liabili- ties", Mathematics of m e r a t i o n s Research, t o a p p e a r .

[12] Young. H.P. 'The design of progressive tax schedules1', College P a r k , Md.:

The University of Maryland School of Public Affairs, 1986.

Referenzen

ÄHNLICHE DOKUMENTE

And then, there is the other, the parallel, community in this play, forged briefly only in the characters ’ lives: the host-guest relationship between Joqola, Zviadauri and

experiment group and the control group. Second, the changes in Federal and State laws, policies, and regulations, such as changes in tax rates and deductions, have the same or

The goal in here is to construct a utility function u that has the following properties: (i) it is bounded below, (ii) it satis…es the Inada condition and (iii) there exists c &gt;

The CANs of TOP Tax system can also check the diversion of funds from one company to another company within the group companies (same promoters). The TOP tax system gives a

When a mining company sells or exports the mined ore or mineral to any other company the transfer of rights of bought ore or mineral will be made online from the mining

The Cassou-Lansing model, described in Chapter V, also settles into a balanced growth path equilibrium in which aggregate output, and the stocks of physical and human

Revenue-oriented governments value tax revenue from savings taxation higher than financial market benefits, for example because they are confronted with severe

(1997) The effect of the proteasome inhibitor lactacystin on the presentation of transporters associated with antigen processing (TAP)-dependent and TAP-independent peptide epitopes