• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

The work of art and its beholder. The methodology of the aesthetics of reception

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Aktie "The work of art and its beholder. The methodology of the aesthetics of reception"

Copied!
17
0
0

Wird geladen.... (Jetzt Volltext ansehen)

Volltext

(1)

9

The Work of Art and Its Beholder

The Methodology of the Aesthetic of Reception

Wolfgang Kemp

URIOUS to see what effect it would have, K. went up to a small side chapel near by, mounted a few steps to a low balustrade, and bending over it shone his torch on the altar-piece. The light from a permanent oil-lamp hovered over it like an intruder. The first thing K.

perceived, partly by guess, was a huge armoured knight on the outermost verge of the picture. He was leaning on his sword, which was stuck into the bare ground, bare except for a stray blade of grass or two. He seemed to be watching attentively some event unfolding itself before his eyes. It was surprising that he should stand so still without approaching nearer to it. Perhaps he had been sent there to stand guard. K., who had not seen any pictures for a long time, studied this knight for a good while, although the greenish light of the oil-lamp made his eyes blink. When he played the torch over the rest of the altar-piece he discovered that it was a portrayal of Christ being laid in the tomb, conventional in style and a fairly recent painting. He pocketed the torch and returned again to his seat.1

In this passage from Franz Kafka's The Trial, everything has in fact been mentioned that comprises the aesthetics of reception, all of the elements, in other words, on which this theory is based and built. There is a work of art, a paint­

ing, which has a location, in a church, in a side chapel, and on an altar. There is a beholder who wants to see the painting and who takes appropriate steps in order to do so. He is disposed, not only because of the environment that he and the work of art share, but also because of his inner preconditions - as a beholder he has a specific gender, presence, and history. Yet the same conditions

180

Originalveröffentlichung in: Cheetham, Mark A. (Hrsg.): The subjects of art history : historical objects in contemporary perspectives, Cambridge 1998, S. 180-196

(2)

The Work of Art and Its Beholder: Methodology of the Aesthetic of Reception

also h o l d true for the w o r k o f art: F r o m the f e w details supplied, w e can conclude that the painting once h a d , and still also has, other functions than the straightforward desire to be observed in the manner described above. T h e suggestion of the painting's alternative raison d'etre represented by the oil lamp, the "eternal light," is felt to be distinctly unsettling to its recipient. O n e c o u l d argue, then, that the w o r k o f art and the beholder c o m e together under m u t u­

ally imbricated spatial and temporal conditions. A p a r t , these conditions are n o t clinically pure and isolatable units. A l t h o u g h their c o m i n g together m a y be ill-starred, a m u t u a l recognition o f each other is assured. In the same w a y that the beholder approaches the w o r k of art, the w o r k of art approaches him, respond­

ing to a n d recognizing the activity of his perception. W h a t he will find first is a contemplating figure o n the other side of the divide. T h i s recognition, in other w o r d s , is the m o s t felicitous pointer to the m o s t i m p o r t a n t premise o f recep­

tion aesthetics: namely, that the function of beholding has already been incorpor­

ated into the w o r k itself. T h e text suggests just h o w m u c h time c o u l d be spent

" i l l u m i n a t i n g " this fact, w h i l e an attention, say, to either the w o r k ' s content or style can n o longer retain a c o m p a r a b l e attraction. K a f k a ' s parable provides us w i t h a clue t o the allure o f reception aesthetics: W h a t his archetypal beholder really felt while contemplating the w o r k remains eternally u n s p o k e n .

Whenever the consideration of reception has come to the fore in art-historical research, it has usually been in the f o r m of studies devoted to the historical reception of w o r k s of art. Reception history, however, issues a m e t h o d o l o g y distinguishable f r o m that employed in reception aesthetics. Let us first consider several approaches to the practice of reception history.

Reception Histories/Psychologies

(1) In the history o f reception, there is a school o f thought that pursues the migration and transformation o f artistic formulas through different artistic c o n ­ texts and historical periods. In its positivist applications, it procures data and establishes earlier influences. It researches the reasons that were decisive in the selection of certain motifs, and it analyzes the differences that inevitably c o m e t o exist between the " o r i g i n a l " and its later "after-images." Derived f r o m the recognition o f h o w artists w o r k every day, inheriting traditions that they then m a k e their o w n , H a r o l d B l o o m (1973) in the arena of literary studies a n d , fol­

l o w i n g h i m , N o r m a n Bryson (1984) in the realm o f visual arts each developed the idea of the d r a m a o f succeeding generations w h o labor under " a n anxiety o f influence." A c c o r d i n g to this branch o f reception history, creative misunder­

standing does not simply occur; given specific historical circumstances, it is both a deliberate and a necessary attitude.

(2) In contrast to this work-specific procedure, a different branch o f re­

ception history deals with the written (and, in a very restricted way, the oral) reactions of both beholders and users o f w o r k s o f art. Even if purely literary-

181

(3)

The Subjects and Objects of Art History

historical goals are not foremost (such as in the intellectual history of art crit­

icism, of writings on art, etc.), one could still expect to find in these kinds of studies contributions to a history of taste and insights into the interaction between art production and art criticism in the broadest sense. Although such an approach has often been valued as highly promising (Bal and Bryson 1991: 184-8), it remains problematic because literary testimonials have only a limited value as sources with regard to the reception of visual art, since they are above all beholden to their literary mission and can only be expressed through that genre. Further­

more, there is the added problem that no one will ever be able to construct a comprehensive art-historical method for deciphering reception/historical state­

ments, given that we possess such sources only for a minimal number of works of art, and also because whole art-historical eras remain silent in this respect.

(3) There is one trend in reception theory that would like to be considered as the authentic history of taste. This particular domain of research analyzes the factual reception of works of art by monitoring the art trade, the theft and destruction of art, and the enterprise of collecting. This approach must, how­

ever, be understood as only part of a more general program, which has as its main object the institutional forms of art reception. In this wider frame­

work, the history of collecting art is accompanied by histories of collections, of museums, of exhibitions, of galleries, of the art trade, and of the presentation and placing of works of art, as well as by historical studies of the institution­

alized behavior exhibited toward works of art.

(4) A further line of demarcation has to be drawn between the aesthetics of reception and the psychology of reception. The latter may study the spectator as its focus, yet it regards the process that occurs between the beholder and the work of art as a physiological or a perceptive one. Along with the aesthetics of reception, perception psychology shares the conviction that the work of art is based upon active completion by its beholder (see Gombrich's "beholder's share," for example) - that is to say that a dialogue occurs between the part­

ners. Psychological studies place this dialogue, however, on the level of a con­

struct created by an exchange between the organ of perception and the form of the work. As a consequence, this kind of approach necessarily entails an ahis- torical way of proceeding. To put it more exactly, this approach removes the process of reception from the conditions of reception. It almost goes without saying that the work of art and the situation of reception make many more specific offers to the beholder than would arise through formal articulation. And the beholder, of course, brings more than his or her open eyes to the perception/

reception of the work of art.

To be sure, reception aesthetics can benefit from the studies of these neigh­

boring disciplines, and it certainly hopes to be able to contribute its share to them. Cooperation, however, cannot hide the fact that a very fundamental dif­

ference in principle exists. Neighboring schools of thought may claim the right to represent the last word in research on actual, individual beholders, not to mention the perceiving public in general. Their interests are aimed at people,

182

(4)

The Work of Art and Its Beholder: Methodology of the Aesthetic of Reception

real beholders, be they the artists w h o appropriate the w o r k o f their predeces­

sors, the critics w h o e x a m i n e their p r o d u c t i o n s , the collectors w h o purchase t h e m , or simply the observers w h o s e optical reactions are directed to the w o r k o f art. M o r e o v e r , the research o n beholders is able to study the effect that art institutions have o n the aesthetic behavior o f the recipients.

Reception Aesthetics

A s it is being used here, however, reception aesthetics enacts its interpretive p o w e r in a w o r k - o r i e n t e d fashion. It is o n perpetual l o o k o u t for the implicit beholder, f o r the f u n c t i o n o f the beholder prescribed in the w o r k o f art. T h e fact that the w o r k has been created " f o r s o m e b o d y " is n o t a novel insight, proffered by a small branch o f art history, but the revelation of a constitutive m o m e n t in its creation f r o m its very inception. Each w o r k o f art is addressed to s o m e o n e ; it w o r k s to solicit its ideal beholder. A n d in d o i n g so, it divulges t w o pieces o f i n f o r m a t i o n , w h i c h , considered f r o m a very high standpoint, are, perhaps, iden­

tical: In c o m m u n i c a t i n g w i t h us, it speaks a b o u t its place and its potential effects in society, a n d it speaks a b o u t itself. Therefore the aesthetics o f reception has (at least) three tasks: (1) it has to discern the signs a n d m e a n s by w h i c h the w o r k establishes contact w i t h us; a n d it has t o read t h e m w i t h regard to (2) their sociohistorical a n d (3) their actual aesthetic statements. In this c o n t e x t , it is i m p o r t a n t to p o i n t o u t , as a specific characteristic o f c o m m u n i c a t i o n in the visual arts, that a u t h o r a n d recipient d o n o t deal w i t h one another directly, as is the case in the daily occurrence o f face-to-face c o m m u n i c a t i o n . " A u t h o r and reader [and beholder] d o n o t k n o w one another, they have o n l y t o think of the respective other. In d o i n g so, b o t h carry o u t an abstraction f r o m the real indi­

viduality, as it is present in the factual d i a l o g u e " (Link 1 9 7 6 : 12). It s h o u l d be evident that this w o r k o f abstraction is permeated, o n b o t h sides, by projec­

tions, a n d that historical a n d societal ideals a b o u t the f u n c t i o n a n d effect of art p l a y a part in it. In this respect, reception aesthetics is prepared to read the appeals and signals that a w o r k of art directs at its beholder.

T o d a y , after a quarter-century of development and testing, reception aesthetics can be viewed as a fully valid apparatus for the study of literature (for general surveys, critical appreciations, and anthologies, see W a r n i n g 1 9 7 5 , L i n k 1 9 7 6 , Iser 1 9 7 8 , Suleiman a n d C r o s m a n 1 9 8 0 , Reese 1 9 8 0 , T o m p k i n s 1 9 8 0 , Jauss 1982, H o l u b 1984). Its application to the study of the visual arts, however, seems less assured, although art historians have done some interesting preliminary w o r k in the field. For the m o s t part, the historiography o f reception aesthetics in art history will s h o w its use to be erratic. N o consistent tradition has been estab­

lished, o n l y a series o f repeated efforts to apply its methodologies. Part o f the p r o b l e m is that reception aesthetics c o n f r o n t s s o m e o f the m o s t basic tenets o f the bourgeois appreciation o f art: those that claim that the w o r k can o n l y be u n d e r s t o o d by or in itself, by the creative process, or by its producer.

183

(5)

The Subjects and Objects of Art History

Origins

Of essential historical importance, although not immediately consequential, was the step that Hegel took in his "Lectures on Aesthetics" (published as a book in 1835) by focusing on the relationship between work and beholder as an impor­

tant factor in his general history of art forms. Whereas eighteenth-century aes­

thetics had called for the nonrecognition of the beholder as the prerequisite for the most intense effect on the beholder (Fried 1980), Hegel here identifies two modes of being for the work of art, which occur necessarily together, yet in different degrees: These are the existence of the work "for itself" and "for us."

Hegel considers their relationships maintained through the historical process, which engenders a "development [of art] for others" in three phases (Hegel 1965, 2: 13ff.). Whereas the "austere style" of the early period remains closed both

"to itself" and to its beholder, the "ideal style" of the classical period opens itself "to us" to such an extent that the recognition of our own presence seems like a gift in a moment of abundance, and not at all like an effort to draw us in and entrap us. In the following phase, during the "pleasing style," the "effect on the outer world" becomes purpose and matter in itself. Art no longer lives in and for itself but for its connections to the outer world.

Alois Riegl (1902) followed Hegel's developmental model in his last work on Dutch group portraiture. His large-scale analysis is dedicated not only to the relationship among the depicted subjects but also to the rapport established with the beholder. Riegl's essay must be regarded as the seminal study of recep­

tion aesthetics in the field of art history. With regard to architectural analysis, however, August Schmarsow had already led the way. As early as 1893, he had described architecture as a "creator of space" and its "spatial construct" as "liv­

ing space," as a kind of space which refers to the elemental orientations of human beings and, above all, to their mobility.

After many decades in which stylistic analysis and iconographic studies were the reigning interpretive paradigms in art history, reception aesthetics finally resurfaced in the late sixties (for a methodology, see Kemp 1983). In the mean­

time, monographic studies have been published that examine the potential of the method for the interpretation of whole eras of art (see Fried 1980, 1990;

Stoichita 1993; Shearman 1993; and for an anthology of relevant interpreta­

tions, see Kemp 1992).

Contemporary Conceptualizations

In the following section, I will attempt to present the scope of reception aesthe­

tics as it is practiced today: in method, conceptualization, and stages of analysis.

It is not only in the power of works of art that an impression can be made on its beholder. Before the dialogue between work and beholder can even begin to transpire, both are already caught in prearranged interpretive spheres, as we saw in Kafka's parable. We have to distinguish between extrinsic conditions of

184

(6)

The Work of Art and Its Beholder: Methodology of the Aesthetic of Reception

access and intrinsic points of reception already in place between the beholder in the church and the beholding knight in the painting. The aesthetic objects are only accessible to both the beholder and the scholar under conditions that are mostly safeguarded by institutions and that, in themselves, require certain patterns of behavior on the part of the recipient. Extrinsic conditions of access comprise, for example, the architectural surround and the corresponding ritual behavior expected by the religious cult, the court, or the bourgeois institutions of art. The task of restoring the work of art to its original environment and its context of comprehension is taken very seriously by reception aesthetics (for case studies, see Kemp 1986, 1994). And it is just as important to discover the processes that can provoke a change in context, that is, not to evaluate the work of art one-sidedly under the conditions of just its first and latest appearance, but to follow work and context throughout the history that they have mutually cre­

ated. As part of this much more general movement in the humanities - what might be called contextualism - reception aesthetics seeks to revive a sensitivity for relationships among phenomena, to train, above all, other senses, especially the "sense for relationship" (Nietzsche).

The institutions, academic studies, and modern techniques of reproduction in modern art have often formed an unholy alliance, one whose intention is to present their objects as unrelated monads - ubiquitous, homeless, displaced - as aestheticians of the twenties and thirties (Valery, Benjamin, Heidegger) already realized with some alarm (Wright 1984). The fact that many works of art in modern times were destined neither for a concrete location nor a spe­

cific addressee does not suggest, however, that analyses undertaken in the aesthetics of reception are without objects. The consideration of a more open reception situation can have as informative an effect on arriving at an inter­

pretation as the information that derives from context-dependent studies. In a classic study, Brian O'Doherty, for example, has shown what tremendous power of definition is ascribed to the "white cube," the gallery space which supposedly recedes to the neutral background in order to let the works of art be effective

"by themselves"; the same space which in reality has "created" modern art, which was the condition of its possibility, and which, unlike any other institu­

tion, has influenced the appearance and reception of modern art even down to its details (O'Doherty 1986). And as far as the works of art that have lost their original destination and appear in new contexts are concerned, it can be stated in a generalized way that the new availability will not succeed in severing com­

pletely the old relationships. Two hundred years of the history of art may have removed the work's ambience - may have severed it from its original forms of presentation and therefore may actually have established it as an art object, after all - yet it will in any case continue to show fossilized remnants of its context markers that position it and the beholder anew. As a historical method of investigation, reception aesthetics is obliged to reconstruct the original recep­

tion situation. In this way it can reverse the processes that had colluded to exclude this approach in general from the history of art appreciation and that also, in a parallel development, had isolated the works of art.

1 8 5

(7)

The Subjects and Objects of Art History

T o return to the beginning: W h a t w e call conditions of access o n the part o f the beholder and institutions c o u l d be called conditions of its appearance o n the part o f the w o r k of art. B o t h are conventional. T h e w o r k reacts t o its spa­ tial and functional context through the m e a n s o f its m e d i u m , through its size, its f o r m , its shaping of the interface or the border between the " o u t s i d e " a n d the " i n s i d e , " its inner scale, the degree of its finish, a n d its spatial disposition (i.e., the m a n n e r in w h i c h it either continues or negates the outer space a n d positions its beholder). A l l these m e c h a n i s m s of transmission and m e d i a t i o n are part o f firmly established conventions or result f r o m practical necessities a n d c a n n o t , or o n l y rarely, be u n d e r s t o o d as a particular achievement o f either a w o r k o f art or an artist. O f course the case in w h i c h changes of c o m m u n i c a ­ tive structures occur should be taken very seriously: It c o u l d indicate paradig­

matic changes in the history o f reception, for example. T h e particular task of interpreting a w o r k o f art according to reception aesthetics starts at the p o i n t o f intersection between " c o n t e x t " and " t e x t " : at the p o i n t , that is, w h e r e the inner w o r k i n g s o f the w o r k of art initiate a dialogue b o t h w i t h its s u r r o u n d ­ ings and its beholders.

I have already pointed o u t that the w o r k of art, contrary to face-to-face c o m ­ munication, produces asymmetrical c o m m u n i c a t i o n . T h i s conclusion is a relative one, because the theory of c o m m u n i c a t i o n does n o t recognize total asymmetry:

It must always posit an opposite partner, must a l w a y s take into account a c o m m o n frame o f reference. In the case o f aesthetic c o m m u n i c a t i o n , relative a s y m m e t r y proves to be the impetus for n o t o n l y situating the beholder - by w a y of exterior arrangements as described a b o v e - but also for stimulating, for activating the beholder to take part in the construction of the w o r k of art. T h i s activation occurs by w o r k i n g through the w a y by w h i c h the beholder becomes part o f the intrapainting c o m m u n i c a t i o n ; m o r e precisely, through the w a y in w h i c h he or she takes part in the c o m m u n i c a t i o n w i t h w h i c h he or she can o n l y be associated as a beholder, n o t as an actor. T h e inner communication, w h i c h w e might call representation, c o m p o s i t i o n , or action, consists o f "people w h o give each other signs . . . , things which are signs . . . , events w h i c h , in them­

selves, already are c o m m u n i c a t i o n or are at least a c c o m p a n i e d by c o m m u n i c a ­ tion or which, o n the other hand, are the object of communication that is created by the people in the p a i n t i n g " (Bitomsky 1972: 30). In contrast t o m o s t kinds of everyday c o m m u n i c a t i o n , the essential characteristic of aesthetic c o m m u n ­ ication is that its inner exchange takes place under the eyes o f the beholders.

" W i t h i n the m e d i u m certain forms have been inserted w h i c h organize the percep­

tion o f the beholders, i.e., the w a y in w h i c h they l o o k at inner c o m m u n i c a t i o n . Inner c o m m u n i c a t i o n is presented a n d , in fact, presented in such a w a y that it n o t o n l y signifies that w h i c h it w o u l d signify for the participating actors of inner c o m m u n i c a t i o n w i t h o u t a n y beholder, but that it has a supplementary m e a n i n g w h i c h results directly f r o m the fact that beholders are present" (ibid., p. 105). T h e opening and presentation of inner c o m m u n i c a t i o n are achieved by means of a structuring that, depending o n whether they address the beholder directly or whether they are conceived for a broader reaction, can be called

1 8 6

(8)

The W o r k of Art and Its Beholder: Methodology of the Aesthetic of Reception

precepts o f reception or offers of reception. T h e term that is really appropri­

ate in this case, however, is implicit beholder: the beholder w h o is intended by these inner orientations and becomes the addressee o f the w o r k o f art.

Forms of Address

(1) First o f all, one has to study the w a y in w h i c h things and persons o f the intrapainting c o m m u n i c a t i o n establish relations w i t h one another while at the same time including or (seemingly) excluding the beholder. T h i s process is called diegesis ( f r o m the Greek, meaning a wide-ranging discussion). Diegesis explains the distribution of the actors o n the canvas a n d / o r in the perspective space, the position that they take t o w a r d one another and t o w a r d the beholder, their gestures a n d visual contacts. In short the deictic arrangement of the w o r k of art refers to its m o d e s of manifesting c o m m u n i c a t i o n and orienting its principal c o m m u n i c a t o r s .

(2) M a n y w o r k s contain figures w h o are, m o r e or less, r e m o v e d f r o m the c o n t e x t o f the internal action or c o m m u n i c a t i o n and w h o have been t h r o w n o n t o the side of the beholder (think of Kafka's knight, for example). T h e y become vehicles o f identification, figurations of the beholder in the painting, repre­

sentatives o f a personal perspective. In narratological terminology, they are the focalizers w h o can address the beholder directly, as figures that l o o k at h i m or her, that p o i n t to h i m or her as well as to something else. But they can also proceed m o r e cautiously and guide h i m or her t o w a r d an event, offer h i m or her their o w n view, a d m i t h i m or her into their o w n ranks. A s a third poss­

ibility, they can be taken o u t o f the representational context and yet cannot be attributed directly to the beholder: A s figures of reflection or diversion, they accomplish m o r e than just pointing or guiding.

(3) T h e classic means of positioning the beholder is u n d o u b t e d l y through the use of perspective in all of its manifestations. It is because of perspective - or the spatial c o m p o s i t i o n o f the painting in general - that the beholder is situ­

ated in relation to the painting, brought into position; a fact that could still be attributed to the d e m a n d s of the exterior orientation. But perspective achieves m o r e than connecting the space o f the beholder w i t h the space of the paint­

ing. In the end, it also regulates the position of the recipient w i t h regard to the inner c o m m u n i c a t i o n ; that is to say, the presentation o f the painting w i t h its d e m a n d s o n h o w it should be viewed.

After Riegl's pioneering studies o n the D u t c h g r o u p portrait (1902), it w a s a b o v e all film analysis, w i t h o u t a c k n o w l e d g i n g Riegl's m o d e l , that developed a c o m p l e x m e t h o d based on the three aforementioned structural elements, in order to find o u t a b o u t the structure of the inner film w o r l d , a b o u t the posi­

tion of the beholder in relation to it, and a b o u t the processes of the construc­

tion of subjectivity and gender roles (Heath 1981; Burgin 1982; M u l v e y in Penley 1986: 5 7 - 6 8 ) . T h e application of this methodological apparatus very quickly

187

(9)

The Subjects and Objects of Art History

reaches its limits in art history, because art (except for a relatively short time in the nineteenth century) prefers ideal positions of the beholder to positions o f actual individuals a n d , unlike film, does n o t build its pictorial w o r l d s f r o m a tightly intermeshed succession of pictures of viewing and pictures of the viewed.

T h i s m e t h o d bears fruit o n l y if it establishes the historical f o r m s of c o m m u­ nication o f a painting b o t h as a v i e w a n d as a staged v i e w structure; that is, as b o t h extra- and intradiegetic conditions o f view.

(4) T h e behavior o f the beholder is also decisively stimulated by the w a y in w h i c h the artistic scene or action is depicted, in its cropping, its details, its fragments. It is o n l y since the fifteenth century that the painting conceived as a fragment has existed, a n d o n l y since the seventeenth century has the inten­

sification o f this effect as a radical cutting into a presumed preexistent reality been the concern of painters. H o w e v e r , that w h i c h w a s practiced as a valid alternative before the fifteenth century, a n d , in fact, l o n g after it - namely, the construction o f the elements t o f o r m the painting - proves to be equally rele­

v a n t in this context. O n e c o u l d take the v i e w that the intended completeness o f the constructed image does n o t ask for the supplementing o f the nonvisible b y its spectator. T h o u g h c o m p l e t i n g the incompleted m i g h t be one w a y o f beholding a painting, it remains the case that every artistic activity entails d r a w ­ ing a border a n d defining itself b y w h a t it has excluded. If the selection o f the painted " f r a g m e n t " is recognized as an intersubjective strategy, then so t o o m u s t be the classification of the realm of the visible according to categories such as exposition versus obstruction, accessibility versus inaccessibility. T h i s p r o ­ cess depends o n whether objects are d e m o n s t r a b l y revealed to or hidden f r o m their beholder, whether they let themselves be observed or deliberately elude visibility, just like everything that exists outside the boundaries o f the painting (Fontanille 1989).

(5) A s the last item o f this s u m m a r y o n f o r m s of address, w e need to iden­

tify the m o s t difficult a n d , by definition, m o s t intangible category, w h i c h can also interact in various w a y s w i t h the previous four. Literary theory refers to the blank or the aesthetics o f indeterminacy, b o t h conceptualizations m e a n i n g that w o r k s o f art are unfinished in themselves in order t o be finished by the beholder (Ingarden 1 9 6 5 , Iser 1 9 7 8 , K e m p 1985). T h i s state o f unfinishedness or indeterminacy is constructed and intentional. But it does m e a n that as spec­

tators w e m u s t complete the invisible reverse side o f each represented figure, or that w e mentally continue a path that is cut off by the frame. In this w a y , everyday perception is n o different f r o m aesthetic perception. T h e w o r k o f art lays a claim to coherence, though, and this impulse turns its " b l a n k s " into i m p o r ­ tant links or causes for constituting meaning. W i t h regard t o texts, but also in a process easily applicable to paintings, this means that the blanks "are the unseen joints of the text, a n d as they m a r k off schemata a n d textual perspectives f r o m one another, they simultaneously trigger acts o f ideation o n the reader's part.

Consequently, w h e n the schemata a n d perspectives have been linked together, the blanks 'disappear.' " Blanks can be regarded as " a n elementary m a t r i x for the interaction between text and reader" (Iser 1 9 7 8 : 1 8 2 - 3 ) .

1 8 8

(10)

The Work of Art and Its Beholder; Methodology of the Aesthetic of Reception

A n Analysis: Nicolaes Maes's The Eavesdropper

Consider a curious drawing that has been recognized for a long time as the work of Nicolaes Maes (1632-93)2 (Fig. 28). The scene is sparse: a curtain, which takes up the entire right half, and, set in an interior, an apparently female figure who is oriented toward the right-hand side, toward what is hidden from view behind the curtain. It might be surprising that this drawing, with its min­

imal repertoire of motifs, served as a preliminary sketch for a painting. The painting itself (45.7 x 71.1 cm), which is signed and dated 1655, simplifies matters for the beholder (Fig. 29).3 The female figure turns out to be the maid, who, coming up from the basement, is pausing, obscured by the newel post.

She is obviously eavesdropping on the events which are unfolding in the back­

ground, in another room of the house. An extended excursion into iconogra­

phy and social history could confirm this interpretation and elaborate on it.

Maes produced a dozen paintings on the theme of the eavesdropper.4 This was his most successful motif in the field of genre painting; in each case the com­

position was only slightly varied. In terms of both the composition and of recep­

tion aesthetics, the figure of the eavesdropper is crucial. Given that she is encoded in multiple ways, the woman clearly belongs to the category of the persona of the beholder, of the personal perspective. She becomes the focus of events by establishing direct eye contact with us from inside the painting. By smiling mischievously and using a gesture that imposes silence, she gives us to under­

stand that we are supposed to behave likewise. Here, the construction of the beholder's presence brings about the extreme possibility of direct interaction.

Whether the direct address to the beholder is achieved or not, however, is regu­

lated by artistic conventions which (in a way that remains to be researched) are certainly connected with general norms of behavior.

Present as beholders, we are asked by the eavesdropper to become voyeurs.

Such a transformation is suited to the medium. We see and do not hear what the eavesdropper hears but cannot see, and we are only seen by her, our accom­

plice, but not by the others in the painting. In this way the personified sender, that is, the eavesdropper, is supposed to trigger in the beholder two simulta­

neous reactions: a particular way of behaving and the shift to visuality. It thus becomes apparent what happens when part of the inner communication func­

tions as a precept of reception. One might almost think that the woman would have to give up her eavesdropping because she is so preoccupied with us. This double role has its price, and here lies the critical point of forced relationships between the painting and its beholder.

It is the eavesdropper's task to make us participate in a communication of which neither she nor we are a part. That is what gives the painting such an exemplary character. If affirms the proposition that is true for the painting as such, and it stresses at the same time what matters with regard to the dif­

ference between the beheld painting (aesthetic perception) and the everyday event that was eavesdropped on or secretly observed (voyeuristic behavior). As already emphasized, the interior communication in the painting is "presented,

189

(11)

The Subjects and Objects of Art History

JJB

Figure 28. Nicolaes Maes, The Eavesdropper (drawing). Pen and ink on paper. Fogg Art Museum, Harvard University. Photo from W. Sumowski, Drawings of the Rembrandt School (New York, 1984).

a n d , in fact, presented in such a w a y that it n o t o n l y signifies that w h i c h it w o u l d signify for the participating actors of inner c o m m u n i c a t i o n w i t h o u t a n y beholder, but that it has a supplementary meaning w h i c h results directly f r o m the fact that beholders are present" ( B i t o m s k y 1972: 105). In the voyeuristic situation, the contrary holds true: Here the situation's supplementary meaning for the v o y e u r results f r o m the fact that the participating actors are n o t aware of his or her presence. Therefore, the re-creation of the voyeuristic situation in the painting is n o t possible; it is o n l y possible to represent it, a n d it is this very difference that gives Maes's painting its n a m e . T h e eavesdropper is seen by us a n d , w h a t is m o r e , challenges our perception, a fact that in itself w o u l d basi­

cally change or diminish her status. In any event, her "supplementary m e a n i n g "

results f r o m the fact that she sees us and is seen by us: T h a t is to say, there exists a perceptual aesthetic exchange. Furthermore, it is logically consistent that a painting of this k i n d is called The Eavesdropper and n o t " T h e C o u p l e that Is Eavesdropped U p o n " or something similar, because w h a t is represented above all is the act of eavesdropping itself, and n o t the interaction w h i c h is both eaves­

d r o p p e d u p o n and observed. A m o n g all the variants that M a e s devoted to this topic, the t w o discussed here speak m o s t plainly in this respect. W h a t is it, after all, that is presented by the eavesdropper in a m a n n e r so pregnant w i t h

190

(12)

The W o r k of Art and Its Beholder: Methodology of the Aesthetic of Reception

Figure 29. Nicolaes Maes, The Eavesdropper, 1655. \T3ht" x i 5" l u " (45.7 x 71.1 cm).

Collection of Harold Samuel, London.

significance? In the drawing, there is nothing - nothing that w e can see. In the painting, there is little - in both cases the curtain hangs in front of the events.

T h e fact that this curtain, illusionistically d r a w n , hangs in front of the paint­ ing gives us an indication that w e are, for the m o m e n t , supposed to ascribe it to the outer and n o t the inner apparatus of the w o r k o f art. Its treatment leads us t o the conditions where w e ought to have started, namely, the conditions of access and appearance. W e are confronted w i t h a panel w h o s e function w a s to decorate the walls o f a residence or o f a collection. Representations of curtains (or, m o r e generally speaking, veils) in w o r k s o f art are as old as the tradition o f painting itself.5 Religious art draws its effect f r o m the dialectic of unveiling a n d concealing; it deals in cult images hidden in the m o s t h o l y places - behind curtains, or in shrines or folding altars w h o s e interiors are opened o n l y o n high feast days. T h e first secular art collectors must simply have taken over the c u s t o m o f veiling: Perhaps they also feared the dangerous luster of the n e w secular art. D u r i n g the c o m p i l a t i o n o f an inventory of m a n y hundreds o f paint­

ings belonging to Margaret o f Austria, w h o w a s one of the first art collectors in the N o r t h , f e w were f o u n d that were " w i t h o u t veil or c o v e r " (sans couverte ne feuillet), as the register f r o m a p p r o x i m a t e l y 1 5 3 0 proclaimed.6 W h e n the secular use o f paintings and collecting secular art became widespread, the o n l y means of assuring a painting's survival w a s to cover it w i t h a curtain. T h i s practice w a s internationally customary: W e find it as far afield as R o m e and

191

(13)

The Subjects and Objects of Art History

Figure 30. Willem van Haecht, The Studio of Apelles, / 628. Oil on canvas. Rubens House, Antwerp. Photo courtesy of the museum.

Antwerp. Seventeenth-century paintings of collections show that there were always some painted works of art that were fitted with such curtains, for reasons of both protection and increasing their aesthetic allure7 (Figs. 30, 31).

The first illusionistically painted picture curtain appears in 1644 in a small painting of the Holy Family by Rembrandt, a work of art that was copied sev­

eral times by Maes.8 From that date on, illusionistically painted picture curtains and frames became ever more numerous for the next two or three decades; both are found in Maes's oeuvre. Thus the painted picture curtain quotes a then- common requisite of art collecting: This alone, however, does not tell the whole story. Owing to the very fact that it is painted, the curtain multiplies, so to speak, the context markers of the work of art. It not only draws the painting into the collection, but also the collection into the painting. The painted cur­

tain transforms the work into a piece of art, an act which represented, perhaps not in our eyes but undoubtedly in the eyes of its first owners and beholders, an enormous increase in value, and which really elevated the painting to its proper place and to the level of debate within the whole of the art collection.

Deception, subterfuge, optical illusion, and surprise were essential qualities of items in a collection: artistic chairs that, once the unsuspecting user had sat down, did not release him or her; goblets that, once filled to the brim, let escape

1 9 2

(14)

T h e W o r k of A r t and Its B e h o l d e r : M e t h o d o l o g y of t h e A e s t h e t i c o f R e c e p t i o n

I

\

dm '

Figure 31. Gabriel Metsu, The Geelvinck Family, ca. 1650. Oil on canvas. Staatliche Museen, Gemaldegalerie, Berlin. Photo courtesy of Bildarchiv Foto, Marburg.

lewd substances or retained their contents in a strange way; paintings that con­

veyed the impression that they were drawn by human hands and were yet found in split rocks or felled trees; still lifes that made their objects palpable and yet were only painted. Their intended effect was not really the illusion but the disillusion, the disillusionment of the beholder. Such deceits brought about sur­

prise, even laughter, but, above all, brought about discussion and argumentation about the numerous modes of reality between appearing and being.

I emphasize this kind of playfulness in order to characterize a historical type of beholder who was not conceived for contemplation, but for dialogue: a beholder conceived for a pleasant exchange between people of his or her own kind and the work of art, a beholder who could also be addressed by the painting in a direct manner. Just consider all of the multilayered aspects of the painted curtain: The painting produces its context as a marker (the work of art has to contribute to the creation of exterior provisions) and as a level of articula­

tion and function (the painting as easel painting and therefore collectible); it 193

(15)

The Subjects and Objects of Art History

confirms the context by quoting it and thus attracting particular attention (competition among the many paintings on the walls of the collection); and it occupies and/or activates the beholder (illusion, disillusion).

Maes adds yet another function, and again, in doing so, he singles out that decisive point that marks the difference between aesthetic and nonaesthetic per­

ception. He uses the external means of reception, that is, the curtain, in artis­

tic recreation, in order to continue the argumentation (which is at least just as artistic) that has started between the beholder and the events in the painting.

This means that he draws the external means to the inside. In terms of devel­

opmental history, this is not without importance: The context marker of the painted curtain is really only a shrunken version of the conditions of access, a small memory of all that once was part of the richness of the aesthetic "pe­

riphery." Now, demonstrably, this remnant is also made functional for the "cen­

ter." In the drawing, the curtain blocks everything that would have been there to see or to hear - a great, bold blank. We must add (almost) everything. Not so in the painting. Here, in the sense of the above-mentioned terminology of Wolfgang Iser, the connectability of segments, of determinate and indeterminate elements, is prepared. Here the curtain has been drawn back to such an extent that half of the eavesdropped conversation becomes visible: A woman who stands behind a table and who, judging from the position of her ams, which she has on her hips, and her head, which she holds at an angle, reproaches a person opposite her. If now, as a result of the eavesdropper's invitation, we became active ourselves in the right half of the painting and lifted the curtain or tried to look behind it in our thoughts, the blank would close and we would really become the eavesdropper's accomplices. That this is not possible, or is pos­

sible "only in thought" - that by the art's grace we have "only" the painting - is made obvious by the curtain, which, as an everyday instrument of veiling and unveiling, yet belongs wholly and doubly to art by being part of the mat­

ter of the painting and, also as the painted curtain, its sign.

Notes

T h i s chapter was translated by Astrid Heyer (University of Western Ontario) and Michael A n n H o l l y (University of Rochester).

1 Franz K a f k a , The Trial (definitive ed.), trans, f r o m the G e r m a n by W i l l a and E d w i n M u i r , rev., with additional chapters and notes by Professor E. M . Butler ( L o n d o n : Seeker and W a r b u r g , 1963), p. 229.

2 See most recently W . S u m o w s k i , Drawings of the Rembrandt School ( N e w Y o r k , 1984), vol. 8, p. 3 9 8 4 .

3 Auctioned off o n J u n e 2 3 , 1967, at Christie's, L o n d o n , to Eduard Speelman Ltd., L o n d o n . N o w Collection of H a r o l d Samuel, L o n d o n .

4 Cf. Beschreibendes und Kritisches Verzeichnis der Werke der hervorragendsten hol- landischen Maler des 17. Jahrhunderts, ed. C. Hofstede de G r o o t , Esslingen, 1915, vol.

6, pp. 520ff. (incomplete list); R i j k s m u s e u m , A m s t e r d a m , Tot lering en vermaak, exhibi­

tion catalog (Amsterdam, 1976), pp. 145ff.; W . R. Robinson, "The Eavesdroppers and Related Paintings by Nicolaes M a e s , " in Holldndische Genremalerei des 17. Jahrhunderts (Berlin:

Staatliche M u s e e n , 1987), pp. 2 8 3 - 3 1 3 ; Stoichita 1993: 7 6 - 8 ; M a r t h a Hollander, " T h e D i v i d e d H o u s e h o l d of Nicolaes M a e s , " Word and Image 10 (1994): 1 3 8 - 5 5 .

194

(16)

The W o r k of A r t and Its Beholder: Methodology of the Aesthetic of Reception

5 For painted picture curtains, see P. Reutersward, "Tavelforhanget," Kunsthistorisk Tidskrift 2 5 (1956): 97ff.; Musee des Beaux-Arts, La peinture dans la peinture, exhibition catalogue ( D i j o n , 1983), pp. 271ff.; W . K e m p , Rembrandt: Die heilige Familie oder die Kunst, einen Vorhang zu Liiften (Frankfurt-on-Main: Fischer, 1986).

6 J . V e t h and S. M u l l e r , Albrecht Diirers niederldndische Reise (Berlin, 1918), vol. 2, p. 83.

Cf. the publication of the inventories in Jahrbuch der Kunstsammlungen des Allerhochsten Kaiserhauses 3 (1885), pp. xciii ff.

7 C f . the reproduction material in S. Speth-Holterhoff, Les peintres flamands de cabinets d'amateurs au XVHe siecle (Brussels, 1957).

8 K e m p , Rembrandt: Die heilige Familie oder die Kunst, einen Vorhang zu Liiften.

R e f e r e n c e s

Bal, Mieke, and N o r m a n Bryson. 1991. "Semiotics and Art History," Art Bulletin 73: 1 7 4 - 2 0 8 . Bitomsky, Hartmut. 1972. Die Rote des Rots von Technicolor, Kinorealitat und Produktions-

wirklichkeit. N e u w i e d - D a r m s t a d t : Luchterhand.

B l o o m , H a r o l d . 1973. The Anxiety of Influence: A Theory of Poetry. N e w Y o r k : O x f o r d University Press.

Bryson, N o r m a n . 1984. Tradition and Desire: From David to Delacroix. Cambridge: C a m­ bridge University Press.

Burgin, Victor. 1982. Thinking Photography. Basingstoke: M a c m i l l a n .

Fontanille, Jacques. 1989. Les espaces subjectifs: introduction a la semiotique de I'observa- teur. Paris: Hachette.

Fried, Michael. 1980. Absorption and Theatricality: Painting and Beholder in the Age of Diderot. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

1990. Courbet's Realism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

G a n d e l m a n , Claude. 1991. Reading Pictures/Viewing Texts. Bloomington: Indiana Univer­

sity Press.

Heath, Stephen. 1981. Questions of Cinema. Basingstoke: M a c m i l l a n .

Hegel, Georg Friedrich W i l h e l m . 1965. Aesthetik, ed. Friedrich Bassenge. 2 vols. Berlin.

H o l u b , Robert C. 1984. Reception Theory: A Critical Introduction. L o n d o n : Methuen.

Ingarden, R o m a n . 1965. Das literarische Kunstiverk. Tubingen: Niemeyer.

Iser, W o l f g a n g . 1978. The Act of Reading: A Theory of Aesthetic Response. Baltimore: J o h n s H o p k i n s University Press.

Jauss, H a n s Robert. 1982. Towards an Aesthetic of Reception. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

K e m p , W o l f g a n g . 1983. Der Anteil des Betrachters: Rezeptionsasthetische Studien zur Malerei des 19. Jahrhunderts. M u n i c h : Maander.

1985. " D e a t h at W o r k : O n Constitutive Blanks in 19th Century Painting," Representa­

tions 10: 1 0 2 - 2 3 .

1986. " M a s a c c i o s Trinitat im K o n t e x t , " Marburger Jahrbuch fur Kunstwissenschaft 21:

4 5 - 7 2 .

1992. Der Betrachter ist im Bild: Kunstwissenschaft und Rezeptionsasthetik. 2nd ed. Berlin:

Reimer.

1994. " T h e Theater of Revolution: A N e w Interpretation of Jacques-Louis David's Tennis Court Oath." In N o r m a n Bryson, Michael A n n H o l l y , and Keith M o x e y (eds.), Visual Culture: Images and Interpretations, pp. 2 0 2 - 2 7 . Hanover, N . H . : Wesleyan University P r e s s / N e w England University Press.

Link, Hannelore. 1976. Rezeptionsforschung. Stuttgart: K o h l h a m m e r .

O ' D o h e r t y , Brian. 1986. Inside the White Cube: The Ideology of the Gallery Space. Santa M o n i c a : Lapis.

Penley, Constance, (ed.). 1986. Feminism and Film Theory. N e w Y o r k and London: Routledge/

BFI Publishing.

Reese, Walter. 1980. Literarische Rezeption. Stuttgart: Metzler.

195

(17)

The Subjects and Objects of Art History

Riegl, Alois. 1902. "Das hollandische Gruppenportrat," Jahrbucb der Kunstsammlungen des Allerhochsten Kaiserhauses 23: 71ff.

Schmarsow, August. 1893. "Das Wesen der architektonischen Schopfung" (1893), in Empathy, Form, and Space. Problems in German Aesthetics, 1873-1893, Santa Monica 1994, pp. 281-98.

Shearman, John. 1993. Only Connect. . . : Art and the Spectator in the Italian Renaissance.

The A. W. Mellon, Lectures in the Fine Arts, 1988; Bollingen Series XXXV, 37.

Washington, D.C. and Princeton: National Gallery of Art/Princeton University Press.

Stoichita, Victor. 1993. L'instauration du tableau. Paris: Meridiens Klincksieck.

Suleiman, Susan R., and Inge Crosman (eds.). 1980. The Reader in the Text. Princeton:

Princeton University Press.

Tompkins, Jane P. (ed.). 1980. Reader-Response Criticism: From Formalism to Post- Structuralism. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Warning, Rainer (ed.). 1975. Rezeptionsasthetik. Munich: Fink.

Wright, Kathleen. 1984. "The Place of the Work of Art in the Age of Technology,"

Southern Journal of Philosophy 22: 565-82.

196

Referenzen

ÄHNLICHE DOKUMENTE

Briefly, the relation between Paul's inconsistencies and Sanders' view can be described as follows 51 : since Paul assumes that Christ is the only way to salvation - for Paul a

In our experience, when classroom practices are transformed by actions generated by both teachers and students, and group solidarity is high, the cogenerative dialogue group

This discusses how the plaster casts were made in ancient times, who and why the first plaster cast collections were needed and how the objects from Classical Antiquity were

This paper will discuss a method for creating a computer-supported, transparent, more reliable way for the estimation of work content, at an early planning stage of a

My enquiry into the different phases of this process highlights two principal strands of reception: on the one hand, Noh theatre has been understood as aesthetic object,

tioned sources are not sufficient he may refer to printed material on diis subject, which he can cite widi criticism. In describing die present state of a monument, die delegate

In the invitation to submit a presentation to the GL-Pro workshop the choice of methodology to be used for assessing the environmental impacts of grain legume production

lenden, halb entblößten Mädchen sind dem Auge des Betrachters ausgeliefert; sie mögen noch so ehrlich in ihren Gefühlen sein (unschuldig sind sie meist gerade nicht