• Keine Ergebnisse gefunden

On the nature of reciprocity : evidence from the ultimatum reciprocity measure

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Aktie "On the nature of reciprocity : evidence from the ultimatum reciprocity measure"

Copied!
14
0
0

Wird geladen.... (Jetzt Volltext ansehen)

Volltext

(1)

On the nature of reciprocity: Evidence from the ultimatum reciprocity measure

Andreas Nicklisch

a,∗

, Irenaeus Wolff

b,c

aUniversityofHamburg&MaxPlanckInstituteforResearchonCollectiveGoods,Bonn,Germany

bUniversityofKonstanz,Germany

cThurgauInstituteofEconomics(TWI),Kreuzlingen,Switzerland

a rt i c l e i nf o

JELclassification:

C91 D03 D63 Keywords:

Distributionalfairness Experiments

Intention-basedfairness Reciprocity

Ultimatumbargaining

a b s t ra c t

Weexperimentallyshowthatcurrentmodelsofreciprocityareincompleteinasystem- aticwayusinganewvariantoftheultimatumgamethatprovidessecond-moverswith amarginal-cost-freepunishmentoption.Forasubstantialproportionofthepopulation, thedegreeoffirst-moverunkindnessdeterminestheseverityofpunishmentactionseven whenmarginalcostsareabsent.Theproportionoftheseparticipantsstronglydependson atreatmentvariation:higherfixedcostsofpunishmentmorefrequentlyleadtoextreme responses.Thefractionsofpurelyselfishandinequity-averseparticipantsaresmalland stable.Amongthevarietyofreciprocitymodels,onlyoneaccommodates(ratherthanpre- dicts)partsofourfindings.Wediscusswaysofincorporatingourfindingsintotheexisting models.

1. Introduction

Despiteatraditionofresearchonreciprocalbehaviorthatspansalmostthreedecades,thedevelopmentoftheoriesof reciprocalbehaviorstillisfarfromcomplete.Oneindicationisthattherehasbeenaproliferationofreciprocitymodels(e.g., Rabin,1993;DufwenbergandKirchsteiger,2004;Sobel,2005;FalkandFischbacher,2006;Coxetal.,2007)thatallseemto fitspecificsituationsbetterthanothers,andyetthereisnoclearindicationofwhichmodeltochooseinwhatsituation.In his2005reviewarticle,Sobelcriticizestheexistingmodelsofreciprocalbehaviorforpresentingautilityfunctionofothers’

andownincomewithoutprovidinganexplanationforhowmuchweightplayersarelikelytoputonothers’incomerelative totheirown.Morespecifically,allofthemodelspositthattheharshnessofareactiontoanunkindactionisdeterminedby thetrade-offbetweenareductionintheotherplayer’spayoffandthecostsofpunishment.Forcostsofpunishmentthatare sufficientlylow,thesemodelsthereforepredicttheharshest-possiblereactiontoeventheslightestdegreeofunkindness.We

WegratefullyacknowledgethemanyusefulcommentsprovidedbyChristophEngel,BerndIrlenbusch,Hans-TheoNormann,theTWIresearchgroup, anassociateeditor,twoanonymousreferees,andtheparticipantsoftheEconomicScienceAssociationmeeting2011inLuxemburg,the4thMaastricht BehavioralandExperimentalEconomicsSymposium2011,andtheEuropeanEconomicAssociationconference2011inOslo.Wearedeeplyindebtedto JörgOechsslerforpushingusintherightdirection,andtheMaxPlanckSocietyforfinancialsupport.

Correspondingauthorat:SchoolofBusiness,EconomicsandSocialScience,UniversityofHamburg,von-Melle-Park5,20146Hamburg,Germany.

Tel.:+4940428388976;fax:+4940428386713.

E-mailaddresses:andreas.nicklisch@wiso.uni-hamburg.de,nicklisch@coll.mpg.de(A.Nicklisch),wolff@twi-kreuzlingen.ch(I.Wolff).

Konstanzer Online-Publikations-System (KOPS) URL: http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:bsz:352-0-320244

https://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2012.10.009

(2)

argue–andshowempirically–thatthisiswrong.However,aslongasthemarginalcostsofpunishmentarestrictlypositive, itisimpossibletofalsifytheabove-mentionedmodelsalongtheselines:itisalwayspossibletoadjustthereciprocation parameterssuchastoaccommodatethedata,giventhereciprocation-parameterdistributionisleftunspecifiedinthemodel expositions.ThissubstantiatesasecondcriticismSobel(2005,p.407)expresses,namelythattheabilityofintention-based modelsofreciprocitytoaccountforexperimentalresultsis“atributetotheirflexibilityratherthanactualsupportforthe formulation.”Tocorroboratetheargument,weintroducetheultimatumreciprocitymeasurewhicheliminatesthemarginal costsofpunishmentaltogether.Ourexperimentaldatashowthatasubstantialproportionofthepopulationdeviatesfrom themodels’extremepreditioninasystematicway,providingvaluableinsightsintohowexistingmodelsneedtobeamended.

Inarecentcontribution,Coxetal.(2008)abandonthedomainofexplicitfunctionalformsandmakeafirststepto addressSobel’s(2005)firstcriticism.Ourexperimentsuggeststhattheirmodelmaybeanimportantstepforward,being abletoaccommodate27–47%ofourobservationsinadditiontowhatcanbeexplainedusingthemoreconventionalmodels.

Nevertheless,themodelstillispronetoSobel’ssecondcriticismofalackofspecificity:aswediscussinSection3,themodel accommodatesratherthanpredictsourobservations.Thewaysinwhich itfailsonthespecificitydomainwillprovide guidancewithrespecttothedirectioninwhichtorefinethemodel.

Anotherquestionthathasattractedincreasedattentionintherecentscholarlydiscussionisthatofpreferencehetero- geneity.Inthecontextofourgame,thisparticularlyconcernstherelativeimportanceofintention-basedreciprocalmotives andinequityaversion(notablyproposedbyBoltonandOckenfels(2000)andFehrandSchmidt(1999)).Dependingonthe situation,oneortheotherseemstodominate.Infact,thereissomeindicationthatbothplayarole:theresultsofthemini- ultimatumgameexperimentsbyFalketal.(2003)andCoxandDeck(2005)demonstratetheimportanceofbothapproaches.

Whentheproposerhastheoptiontoofferanequaldistributionofearningsandanunequalonefavoringherself,therespon- derrejectsthelattersignificantlymoreoftenthanwhentheproposerhastochoosebetweentheunequalandanevenmore unequaldistributionofearnings(inFalketal.,44.4%versus8.9%).Obviously,thisresultpointstotheimportanceofreci- procity.However,whentheproposerhasnooptionbuttochoosetheunequaloffer,stillasubstantialnumberofresponders (18%)reject.Asthereisnointentiontofavorherselfonthepartoftheproposer,thisobservationsuggeststhatinequity aversionisasecondempiricallyrelevanttriggerforrejections.Otherexperimentshaveshownsimilarpatterns(e.g.,onthe convexultimatumgame,Andreonietal.(2003),onthree-personultimatumgames,Bereby-MeyerandNiederle(2005),and onathree-persongiftexchangegame,ThöniandGächter(2007)).

Theultimatumreciprocitymeasure(urmgame)hasthefollowingstructure:aproposermakesaproposalofhowtodivide anendowmentE.1Therespondercaneitheracceptorreject.Inthefirstcase,theproposalisimplemented,inthesecond, theresponderobtainsafixedfraction,<1,oftheofferxandfreelychoosestheproposerpayofffromtheinterval[0, E−x].Theimportantfeatureoftheurmgameisthat(incontrasttomostothergameswithpunishmentintheliterature) punishmentisfreeofmarginalcosts,onlycomingatacostthatisfixedoncetheofferismade.2Thisfixedcostiseither equaltohalftheofferortothreequartersoftheoffer,dependingonthetreatment.Aswewillshowbelow,modelsof inequity-aversionandreciprocityleadtoverydifferentpredictionsforbehaviorintheurmgame:thefirstclassofmodels predictsthatresponders–iftheyrejectanoffer–leavetheproposerswithapayoffwhichequalstheirearnings.Incontrast, themajorityofreciprocitymodelspredictsthatrespondersleavetheproposerswithzeroearnings.

Theresultsweobtainarestriking.Lessthan10%oftheobservationscanbecharacterizedasstemmingfrompayoff- maximizers,modelsofinequityaversionaccountfor16–18%,conventionalmodelsofreciprocityfor17–38%.3Atthesame time,wefindasubstantialfractionofafourthtypethatdeviatesfromthesepredictionsinasystematicway,whichwecall gradualreciprocators.Theseplayersarecharacterizedbypunishmentpatternsthatleavetheirproposerswithpayoffsthat areincreasingintheoffermadebutgenerallyleadtounequalpayoffs.Moreover,thefractionoftheseplayersisdetermined bythetreatmentparameter.Inthetreatmentwithahighfixedcostofpunishment,20%ofthepopulationseemtoswitch frombeinggraduallyreciprocaltoconformingtoconventionalreciprocitymodels.Theseobservationscallforanextension ofexistingmodelsofreciprocityinthespiritofSobel’sfirstcriticism:acharacterizationofthesituationthatleadstothe predictionofthetypedistributioninducedbythesituation.

InSection5,wediscussanumberofapproaches ofhowtomodifytheexistingmodelsinlightofourobservations.

Inparticular,wecharacterizethegradual-reciprocatortypewithintheframeworkofCoxetal.(2008),havingdismissed theideaofmatchingtheother’sdegreeofkindnessduetoalackofobservationsofthecorrespondingresponse-pattern predictions.Withrespecttoourtreatmenteffect,wenotethatwhatappearsasanauxiliaryassumptionthatis“sometimes (...)useful”(Coxetal.,2008,p.34)seemstobeanessentialingredientofatheoryofreciprocalbehavior.Asanalternative, weproposethesituation’scoercivenessasapromisingexplanation,definedintermsofthegapbetweenthehighestpayoff theplayercanobtaininthegivensituationandthenext-lowerobtainablepayoff.Anevaluationoftheidea’spredictive power,however,isbeyondthescopeofthisarticleandisleftforfutureresearch.

Theremainderofthepaperisorganizedasfollows:Section2introducestheurmgameandpresentstheexperimental designandprocedure.Section3analyzesthegameaccordingtothepayoff-maximizationmodel,inequityaversion,and

1AsymbolstablecanbefoundinAppendixA.

2Forgamesthatallowforachangeintheotherplayer’spayofffreeofmarginalcosts,cf.,e.g.,EngelmannandStrobel(2004),orFismanetal.(2007), whoexaminethisquestioninthedictatorgame.

3Notethatwedonotconsidertheproposersinourgame;cf.Section3.

(3)

Proposer

0 E

x Responder

accept reject

0 E κx

y

{E x, x} {y, κx}

{ , }:π π

Fig.1. Gametreeoftheultimatumreciprocitymeasure.

severaltypesofreciprocitymodels,alwaysfocusingonresponderbehavior.Subsequently,weanalyzetheexperimentaldata withrespecttothesepredictionsandpointtotheexistenceofaplayertypethathasreceivedlittleattentionintheliterature sofarinSection4.InSection5,weexplorepossibledirectionsinwhichtoextendexistingmodelsofreciprocalbehaviorto enablethemtopredictthekindofbehaviorobserved.Finally,wesummarizeourfindingsandconcludeinSection6.

2. Thegame,experimentaldesign,andprocedure 2.1. Theultimatumreciprocitymeasure(urmgame)

Liketheclassicultimatumgame,theurmgamehastwoplayers,aproposerandaresponder.Theproposerisgivenan endowmentofEandoffersx,0≤x≤E,totheresponder.Iftheresponderacceptstheoffer,theproposerkeepsE−x,while theresponderearnsx.Iftheresponderrejectstheoffer,theresponderearnsx(theconflictpayoffcr)withacommonly knownparameter∈[0,1),whiletheproposer’sconflictpayoffcpisanyamounty,y∈[0,E−x],whereyisfreelychosen bytheresponder.Therefore,thepayofffunctionsfortheproposer,p,andtheresponder,r,respectively,are

p =

E−x, incaseofacceptance

y, otherwise, and

r =

x, in caseofacceptance x, otherwise.

Fig.1illustratesthegametreeoftheurmgame.Notethatrestrictingtheresponsesettoy=0andsetting=0yieldsthe standardtwo-personultimatumgame(Güthetal.,1982).Duetotheserestrictions,thestandardultimatumgameprovides littleinformationaboutnegativereciprocityasadriverforrejection(sinceitreducestheresponder’sdecisiontoachoice betweenonlytwoalternatives).Incontrast,byimposingnomarginalcostsonresponderstoalterproposers’payoffsafter arejection,the‘unrestricted’urmgameisabletoprovideaverydetailedpictureofparticipants’motivationsforrejections (aswillbecomeclearfromthediscussionoftheoreticalpredictionsinthenextsection).Inparticular,thelackofatrade-off betweenownmonetaryincomeandproposerpayoffprovidesnewinsightsintothenatureofother-regardingpreferences.

2.2. Experimentaldesignandprocedure

Eachparticipantplayedoneanonymousurmgameeitherintheroleoftheproposerorintheroleoftheresponder.Inthe instructions,wereferredtoproposersaspersonAandtorespondersaspersonB.ThepiesizewassettoE=12Euros.Offers couldonlybemadeinintegers.Inordertoanalyzeindividualheterogeneityofresponsescorrespondingtodifferentoffersin greaterdetail,weappliedthestrategy-vectormethodtoelicitresponders’choices(Selten,1967).Thismeansthatresponders hadtomakeadecisionforeachpossible(integer)offerbeforetheywereinformedabouttheactualoffer.Then,theofferand thecorrespondingresponderdecisiondeterminedthepayoffs.Thisprocedureimpliedthatrespondershadtomakeatotal of13acceptance/rejectiondecisions.Additionally,theyhadtodeterminethepayoffofproposersforanyoffersrejected.

Incontrasttothestandardprocedureofthestrategy-vectormethod,responderswerenotprovidedwithachoicemenu, thatis,adecisionsheetthatpresentsallpotentialoffersinanascendingordescendingorder.Rather,potentialofferswere presentedsequentiallywithoutapossibilityofreviewingearlierdecisions,andtheorderofpossibleoffersdifferedrandomly forallresponders.Weintroducedthisprocedureforseveralreasons.Theone-by-oneprocedurewaschosentomakeeach decisionassalientaspossible.Further,elicitingdecisionsonebyoneincombinationwitharandomorderwasintendedto keepanypotentialexperimenter-demandeffectsmallbyisolatingdecisionsasmuchaspossible:to‘smoothen’aresponse- patternoveralldecisionsoutofatasteforconsistencywouldinflicthighcognitivecostsonparticipants.Consequently,a smoothresponse-patternshouldonlybeobservedifparticipantsexhibitedunderlyingpreferencesgivingrisetoit.Finally, theorderwasrandomlydeterminedforeachparticipantindividually,inordertocontrolforpossibleordereffects.

(4)

Theexperimentstartedsuchthatcopiesoftheinstructionswerehandedouttoparticipantsandreadaloud.Subsequently, participants’questionsconcerningtheexperimentswereansweredprivatelybytheinstructors.Finally,allparticipantshad toansweranelectronicquestionnairetestingtheirunderstandingofthegameandthepayoffstructure.4Beforeparticipants answeredthequestionnaire,itwasmadeclearthattheonlypurposeofthequestionnairewastoimprovetheunderstanding oftherulesofthegame.Wronganswerswereprivatelyexplainedandcorrectedbeforetheexperimentstarted.

Aftertheyhadmadeallpayoff-relevantdecisions,responderswereaskedtostatewhichoffertheyconsideredasfair, andwhichoffertheyexpectedtoreceive.Subsequently,werandomlymatchedeachrespondertoaproposerandpayoffs wererealizedaccordingtothedecisionsmade.Participantswereinformedabouttheirpayoffsandaskedtoanswerashort socio-demographicquestionnaire,beforeprivatelybeingpaid.

Inordertolearnmoreaboutthenatureofreciprocalpreferences,weplayedthegameundertwotreatmentconditions.

Inthehigh-condition,thecommonlyknownparameterwassetto=0.5,whileinthelow-condition,weset=0.25.

Aswewillshowbelow,this(ratherinnocent)variationhaslittleimplicationforthepredictionsoftheconsideredsocial- preferencemodels,whilethereareimportantdifferencesinactualbehavior.Intotal,76pairsofproposersandresponders participatedinthehigh-treatment,whilewehad77pairsinthelow-condition.

ThelaboratoryexperimentswereconductedattheEconLabattheUniversityofBonn,Germany,inOctoberandNovember 2006.5Intotal,306participantsparticipated;50%oftheparticipantswerefemale,themedianagewas23years.Participants weremostlyundergraduatestudentsfromvariousfieldsofstudies.Approximatelyonethirdofthestudentswereeconomists ormathematicians.Furtherinformationconcerningthesocio-demographicbackgroundoftheparticipantsissummarized intheonlinesupplementarymaterial(availableonthejournal’swebsite).Averagepaymentwas5.15Euros(noshow-up fee)foranaveragedurationof30min,includingtheinstructiontimeandthetimeforpayingparticipants.

3. Theoreticalpredictions

Ourcentralresearchinterestliesintheempiricalanalysisofreciprocalbehavior.Forthisreason,wewillfocusonthe behaviorofrespondersthroughoutthepaper.Proposerbehaviorisunsuitableforourpurposes:proposalsreflect both proposers’other-regardingpreferencesaswellasproposers’strategicconsiderationsconcerningtheother-regardingpre- ferencesofresponders.

Wewillanalyzeresponders’best-responsefunctionsaccordingtoallmajormodelsthatarepotentialcandidatesfor theexplanationofreciprocalbehavior.Forbrevityandeaseofexposition,werefrainfrompresentingthecompletesetsof equilibriaastheydonotshedfurtherlightonourresearchquestion.Inthefollowing,wediscussthree(groupsof)models, the‘standard’game-theoreticprediction,modelsofinequity-aversion,andintention-basedmodelsofreciprocalbehavior.

Beforewedoso,letusclarifysomenotation.Ifamodelpredictsrejectionofanoffer,itwillhavetospecifyavalueforthe responseythatmaybedifferentdependingontheoffer.Toreflectthis,wewillwritey=y(x)todenotethe(offer)response function.Yet,thereisasecondwaytothinkaboutresponses,whichwillproveusefulparticularlyinthecontextoftreatment comparisons.Forthispurpose,weintroducetheconflict-payoffresponsefunction(definingtheresponseyintermsofthe conflictpayoffrc=x),whichwewilldenotebyy=(cr).

3.1. Purepayoff-maximizingpreferences

Thebestreplyofaresponderexclusivelydrivenbymaterialself-interestisobvious:given0<<1,wehavex>xfor anyx>0,andx=xforx=0.Consequently,payoff-maximizingresponders’bestreplyistoalwaysacceptanypositiveoffer x,andarbitrarilyacceptorrejectaproposalofx=0.Giventhisfeature,wewillnotobservevaluesofyfortheseplayers.Ifat all,weobserveavalueforyinresponsetox=0;however,thetheorydoesnotgiveanypredictionforthisvalue.Therefore, payoff-maximizingresponders’best-responsefunctionisgivenbybrpm:x→(ı,y),whereı∈{0,1}representsrejection,ı=0, oracceptance,ı=1:

brpm(x)=

(1,.) ifx>0,

,y) ifx=0, (1)

where(ı,y)∈

(ı,y)|ı∈{0,1},y∈[0,E]

.Ofcourse,notreatmentdifferencesareexpected.

3.2. Inequity-aversepreferences

Inafirststep,notethatinequity-averseresponderswillalwayschoosetoequalizepayoffsafterarejection,sinceitis costlesstoaltertheproposer’spayoffoncethecostsofrejectingaresunk.Inotherwords,theirresponseywillbey(x)=xfor allrejectedoffersx.Whichofferswillberejected?BoththemodelbyFehrandSchmidt(1999)andbyBoltonandOckenfels (2000)predictacceptedoffersxtocomefromaconvexset[x;x],where0≤x<E/2<x≤E.Thespecificvaluesofxandx

4TranslationsoftheGermaninstructionsandthequestionnaireareprovidedintheonlinesupplementarymaterial(availableonthejournal’swebsite).

5ExperimentswerecomputerizedusingzTree(Fischbacher,2007).Fortherecruitmentofparticipants,weusedORSEE(Greiner,2004).

(5)

dependontheparametersofthemodel,notablyon(sinceitdeterminesthemonetaryearningsincaseofaconflict)and theimportancetheindividualresponderplacesonequityconcerns.Toindicatethedependencebetweenxand,andxand ,wewillwritexandx.Bothmodelswouldsuggesttheretobeheterogeneityinthecut-offvaluesforrejections,whileall modelsofinequityaversionmaketheuniquepredictiony(x)=x.Insummary,weobtainthefollowingbest-replyfunction bria:x→(ı,y):

bria(x)=

(0,x) ifx>xorx<x,

(1,.) ifx≤x≤x. (2)

Thepredictedtreatmenteffectsareevident:anincreaseinshiftsbothacceptancethresholds‘inwards’towardstheegali- tarianpayoffdistribution(E/2,E/2).Withrespecttoresponsesasafunction(cr)ofconflictpayoffs,notreatmentdifferences areexpected.

3.3. Intention-basedpreferences

Forourdiscussionofthesemodels,wesub-dividethisclassintofoursub-classes:(i)oneinwhichutilityfunctionsconsist ofalinearcombinationofownincomeandareciprocityterm(whichitselfisaproductofseveraltermsasdescribedbelow, cf.Rabin,1993;Levine,19986;DufwenbergandKirchsteiger,2004;FalkandFischbacher,2006),(ii)thenon-linearmodel ofCoxetal.(2007),(iii)modelsmixingreciprocityconcernsandinequalityaversion,andfinally,(iv)themodelpresented byCoxetal.(2008).

‘Linear’reciprocitymodels.Inthemodelssubsumedunderthisclass,utilityisalinearcombinationofownincomeand reciprocity.Here,reciprocityisaproductofthreeterms.Thefirstweightstheimportanceofreciprocalbehaviortothe person.Thesecondtermcapturesthekindnessoftheotherplayer’spastbehavior.Offersarerankedfromunkind(i.e.,small) tokind(i.e,large)ones,suchthatthetermforanofferwhichisneitherkindnorunkindiszeroandincreases(decreases) monotonicallywitheachrankabove(below)thatoffer.Consequently,unkindoffershavenegativevaluesandkindoffers havepositivevalues.Thethirdtermmeasuresthedegreeofkindnessintheperson’sreaction.Again,responsesareranked suchthataresponsethatisneitherkindnorunkindcorrespondstoavalueofzero,andresponsesabove(below)thatleadto valuesincreasing(decreasing)monotonicallywitheachrank.Duetothemonotonicityofkindness,acceptedoffersforman interval:ifrejectinga(un)kindofferyieldslessutilitythanacceptance,rejectingaless(un)kindofferyieldsalsolessutility thanacceptance.

Atthetimeoftheresponder’sdecisionintheultimatumreciprocitymeasure,thereciprocityweightandthekindness termintheactingplayer’sutilityfunctionarefixed.Consequently,maximizationofutilityincombinationwiththepossibility ofchoosingtheproposer’spayofffreeofmarginalcostimpliesthefollowingforrejectedoffers:thebestreplytoanyunkind offerxmustbethemostunkindresponsepossible,thatis,y(x)=0,∀x<x.Conversely,anyrejectedkindoffermustbe answeredwithy(x)=E−x,∀x>x,thekindestresponsepossible.Inotherwords,therecannotbearejectionfollowedbya responsey(xr),sothat0<y(xr)<E−xr.Asfortheinequity-aversionmodelsabove,theswitchingpointbetweenacceptance andrejectionisplayer-specificandgenerallycannotbepredicted.Thepredictedbest-replyfunctionbrrl:x→(ı,y)isgiven by:

brrl(x)=

⎧ ⎪

⎪ ⎩

(0,E−x) ifx>x, (1,.) ifx≤x≤x

(0,0) ifx<x.

(3)

Notreatmentvariationsarepredictedwithrespecttoy(x)or(cr).Theloweracceptancethresholdxriseswith,asa highermakesrejectionlesscostly.Atthesametime,thereisnoclearpredictionwithrespecttox:whileahigherimplies ahigher‘conflict’payoffx,italsoleadstoalowerpotentialforrewardingactions:E−x<E−xfor>.Therefore,the signofthechangeintheupperacceptancethresholddependsontheweighttheresponderplacesonreciprocity.

Non-linearmodelsofreciprocity.EventhoughCoxetal.(2007)proposearemarkablemodelthatgeneralizestheabove reciprocity-modelsinanimportantway,ityieldsthesamepredictionsforresponderbehaviorintheultimatumreciprocity measureasthe‘linear’reciprocitymodels.Infact,utilityisagainalinearcombinationofownincomeandareciprocity term,wherethelattermultipliestheproposer-payoffwithan“emotional-state”function.isafunctionoftheproposer’s previousbehavior,andtherefore,afixedfactoratthetimeoftheresponder’sdecision.Consequently,theargumentsfrom ourdiscussionofthe‘linear’modelscarryoverandhence,thepredictedbest-replyfunctionhasthesameformasEq.(3) above.

6Strictlyspeaking,themodelofLevine(1998)isdifferentfromtheothermodelslistedinanumberofimportantaspects.However,thebestrepliesare verysimilar,givenLevine(1998)definesaplayer’sutilityfunctionasalinearcombinationofallplayers’monetarypayoffs.

(6)

my money

your money

6 5

4 3

2 1

0

086421012

payoff set for rejections n HIGHκ

offer payoff set for reject ons in LOWκ

Fig.2.Payoffspaceforresponders.

Mixedapproach.AspecialvariationofreciprocitymodelsistheapproachbyCharnessandRabin(2002)whichmixes reciprocityconcernsandinequalityaversion.7Inthismodel,aresponder’sutilityfunctionaddsownpayoffandtheproposer’s payoff,weightedbyatermthatintegratesinequalityaswellasreciprocityconcerns.Inparticular,thisweightislowered iftheproposerreceivesmoremoneythantheresponderandiftheproposermisbehaves.However,eveniftheweightfor reciprocitydependsonthedegreeofmisbehavior(asintheextendedmodelintheappendixofCharnessandRabin,2002), thesumofweightsiseitherpositiveornegative.8 Onceagain,thesameargumentsasforthe‘linear’reciprocitymodels apply,leadingtothesamepredictions.

Generalapproachtoreciprocity.Coxetal.(2008)presenttheirnovelapproachtoreciprocalbehaviorwithintheframework oftheproposer-payoff–responder-payoffspace.Inthisspace,thechoicesetSoftheresponderconsistsofonepointandaray paralleltotheproposer-payoffaxis.Thepointdescribestheoffer,whiletheraycharacterizespossiblepayoffcombinations incaseofarejection,asdepictedinFig.2.Noticethatourtreatmentvariationdoesnotchangethelocationofthepoint,but shiftstherayinlow-closertotheproposer-payoffaxiscomparedtothesituationinhigh-.

Responderpreferencesarerepresentedbyindifferencecurves∈,whereisaplayer’sindifference-curvesetfor agivensituation.Toillustrate,indifferencecurvesofpayoff-maximizingplayersarelinesparalleltotheproposer-payoff axis,thoseofinequity-averseplayersareeitherconvex(BoltonandOckenfels,2000)orpiece-wiselinearwithakinkat the45-degreeline(FehrandSchmidt,1999),indifferencecurvesinthe‘linear’reciprocitymodels(aswellasinthe‘mixed’

modelbyCharnessandRabin,2002)arestraightlinesthatareeitherupward-sloping(negativereciprocity)ordownward- sloping(positivereciprocity),whilethemodelofCoxetal.(2007)generalizesthe‘linear’reciprocitymodelsbyallowing theindifferencecurvestobenon-linear;however,theirslopecannotchangesigns.Irrespectiveoftheirshape,indifference curvesalwayscanberankedsuchthatissaidtobe‘higher’thanifpointsassociatedwitharepreferredtopoints associatedwith.Finally,wheneverwetalkaboutthe-definedpointinS,wemeanthepointassociatedwiththehighest indifferencecurveinwhichstillisinthechoicesetS.9

AtthecenteroftheapproachbyCoxetal.(2008)aretwobasicdefinitions,oneconcernsperceivedkindnessandthe otherkindnessin(re-)actions.First,letusdefineperceivedkindness,or“generosity”.Inthismodel,thenotionofgenerosity isattachedtoresponders’opportunitysets,or,moreprecisely,toopportunitysetsaftertheyhavebeenalteredbytheaction oftheproposer.10Particularly,considerthesetSxofpossiblepayoffcombinations(p,r)whichproposerandresponder cangainaftertheproposerhaschosenx.Letusdefine ˆi(x)=sup

i Sxfori=p,r.AsetSxiscalled“moregenerousthan”a setSx if(i) ˆr(x)−ˆr(x)≥0and(ii) ˆr(x)−ˆr(x)≥ˆp(x)−ˆp(x).Inotherwords,theproposerismoregenerousby choosingxthanbychoosingxif(i)theproposer’schoiceofxoverxdoesnotleadtoadecreaseinthemaximumpayoff

7Infact,theapproachbyFalkandFischbacher(2006)alsorepresentsamixtureofreciprocityandinequalityconsiderations,asreciprocationbythe responderistriggeredbyproposerchoicesthatleadtounequalpayoffs.

8Thisassertionisnotcompletelycorrect.Underaspecificparametercombination,theextendedmodelintheappendixofCharnessandRabin(2002) allowsforrejectionsinconjunctionwithresponderutilityincreasinginproposerincomeifthelatteriscloseto0,anddecreasingifitisaboveathreshold ofxb,wherebmeasureshowstronglyanundeservingpoorestsocietymemberisdisregarded.Inthatcase,responsesarepredictedtobey(x)=max{0, xb},i.e.,theresponsefunctionisparalleltotheresponsefunctionofaninequity-averseplayer(neglectingthecornersolutionsforlowx).Aswefind onlytwooutof153participantsinourdatawhoseresponsepatternisinlinewiththisprediction(apartfromtheinequity-aversionequivalentb=0),we holdthatthisspecialcasecanbeneglectedforeaseofexposition.Thespecificparameterconstellationrequiresthatthecombinedweightplacedona Rawlsiansocialoptimum,ı,isclosetoone(butı<1),thespiteparameterwithrespecttoundeservingplayers,f,issufficientlysmall,f<ı/(1ı),andthe undeservingarenotdisregardedinthetotal-surplus-maximisingpart,i.e.,k0fortheparameterkmeasuringthediscountingofundeservingproposers’

payoffsinthispart,norintheRawlsiansocial-welfarepart,i.e.,b<xforsomerejection-worthyoffers.

9Wedonotrefertothispointasthetangentialpoint,asincaseofacceptanceaswellasforsomeofthemodels,itwouldbeinadequatetospeakof tangents:therecannotbeatangenttoapoint,andinsomecases,the(highest)indifferencecurvewillhaveakinkatthe-definedpoint.

10Strictlyspeaking,thenotionofanopportunitysetasusedbyCoxetal.(2008)wouldruleoutapplicationoftheirmodeltoourgame,astheyrequire opportunitysetstobeconvex.However,wedonotseewhynon-convexityofopportunitysetswouldleadtoproblemsintheanalysis.Hence,wedropthe convexityassumption,asweareconvincedthattheirmodelisanimportanttooltounderstandbehaviorinourgame.

(7)

(a)

my money

your money

0 1 2 3 4 5 6

024681012 (b)

my money

your money

0 1 2 3 4 5 6

024681012

Fig.3.Indifferencecurves(a)and(b)(beingmorealtruisticthan).

therespondercanearn,and(ii)theincreaseofresponder’spayoffasaresultofdecisionxcomparedtoxisnotlessthanthe correspondingincreaseintheproposer’spayoff.Accordingtothisdefinition,anofferxintheurmgameismoregenerous thanxifandonlyifx≥x.

Second,letusdefinekindnessinaction,whichistermed“altruism”.Altruismreferstototheresponder’sutilityfunction ur(r,p)andthecorrespondingcurvatureoftheresponder’sconvexindifferencecurvesinthepayoff-space{(p,r)}.

Forconvenience,itisdefinedintermsofaplayeri’swillingness-to-payforamarginalincreaseinthepayoffofplayerj, WTPi=[∂ui(i,j)/∂j]/[∂ui(i,j)/∂i],ratherthani’smarginalrateofsubstitutionMRSi=1/WTPi.Theresponder’sutility functionur(r,p)issaidtobe“morealtruisticthan”ur(r,p)ifWTPr≥WTPr,∀(r,p).Equivalently,theutilityfunction associatedwithindifferencecurvesismorealtruisticthanthefunctionassociatedwithif,comparedto,thecurves inarerotatedcounter-clockwise(compareFig.3).Asaconsequence,theproposerpayoffpinthe-definedpointin Sxmustnotbesmallerthanpinthe-definedpointinthesameset.

Withinthisframework,reciprocityisdefinedasfollows:aproposer’sdecisionleadingtoSxratherthanSx(Sxbeing moregenerousthanSx)inducesindifferencecurvesratherthanonthepartoftheresponder(withur(r,p)more altruisticthanur(r,p)).Looselyspeaking,moregenerousoffersleadtomorealtruisticpreferences.

Havingoutlinedthemodel,wenowapplyittotheurmgame.Recallthattheconvexindifferencecurvesarerotated clockwiseforlessgenerousoffers.Thatis,thesmallertheoffer,thesteeper–orflatter,incaseofupward-slopingcurves –theindifferencecurves.Asaconsequence,theintersectionbetweenthehighestindifferencecurveandthechoiceset decreasesorremainsconstant,butneverincreasesintheproposer-payoffdimensionforoffersofdecreasinggenerosity.11 Sincealteringtheproposer’spayoffiscostlessandinf

pSx=0,∀x(i.e.,thelowerboundofthechoicesetdoesnotchangefor differentoffers)wecanconcludethatfortworejectedoffersxandxsuchthatx>x,y(x)≥y(x)musthold.

Whichofferswillberejected?Likeinanyoftheothermodelspresented,themodelproposedbyCoxetal.(2008)assumes thatutilityfromownincomeistradedoffagainstasecondutilitycomponentthatisinfluencedbyothers’income.Ifthe responderrejectsanoffer,theutilitygainsfromthissecondcomponentmustoutweighthedecreaseinone’sownincome.

Hence,therespondermusthaveapositiveWTPinresponsetoverygenerousoffers(e.g.,rejectingx≥xandrespondingby y>E−x)–althoughthisscenarioappearshardlyintuitiveatthefirstglance–orhaveanegativeWTPforpinresponse toveryungenerousoffers(e.g.,rejectingx≤xandrespondingbyy<E−x),sothatacceptedofferscomefromaconvexset [x;x].Thespecificvaluesofxandxagaindependontheimportancetheindividualresponderplacesonreciprocity.Thus, weobtainthefollowingbest-replyfunctionbrre:x→(ı,y):

brre(x)=

(0,y(x)) ifx>xorx<x,

(1,.) ifx≤x≤x. (4)

wherey(x)mustsatisfy∂y/∂x≥0.

Withrespecttotreatmenteffects,wefirstturntochangesintheoffer-responsefunctiony(x).Inresponsetoanincrease in,themodelallowsforbothmonotonicincreasesandinvarianceatanygivenlevel,merelyrulingoutreductionsinthe

11Strictlyspeaking,thisargumentrequirespreferencestohavetheincreasingbenevolenceproperty,whichCoxetal.(2008)defineasawillingnesstopay fortheotherplayer’sincomethatdoesnotdecreaseinownincome.

(8)

my money

6 5

4 3

2 1

0 your money 086421012

payoff set for rejections in LOWκ

payoff set for rejections in HIGHκ

offer

Fig.4. Examplefortheinfluenceofavariationonofferacceptance.

response.12Turningtotreatmenteffectsontheconflict-payoffresponsefunction,recallthatourtreatmentvariationdoes notalterthesupremumofrinthesetSxforagivenofferx,sincethevalueofchangestheray,butnotthepoint(i.e.,the offer,whichdefinesthesupremum).Hence,thetreatmentvariationdoesnotchangethegenerosityofoffers.13Ontheother hand,thesameconflictpayoffcrisassociatedwithdifferentoffersinthedifferenttreatments:underalow,ahigheroffer isassociatedwiththesameconflictpayoffthanunderahigh.Atthesametime,higheroffersareattachedtohigherlevels ofgenerosityandtherefore,metwithhigherdegreesofaltruism.Asaconsequence,theconflict-payoffresponsefunction (rc)maydifferbetweenthetreatments:for<,thesameconflictpayoffcr=x=ximplies(x)≥(x).

Withrespecttoacceptancethresholds,themodelpredictsadecreaseoftheacceptancethresholdxfordecreasing.To seethis,taketheofferxthatmakestheresponderindifferentbetweenacceptingandrejectingunder.Letusnowdecrease .Recallthatachangeinleavestheresponder-payoffsupremumunaffectedandhence,indifferencecurvesdonotchange astheresponder’sdegreeofaltruismremainsthesame.Butwiththeindifferencecurvesremainingthesameandtheray ofSxshiftingleft,therespondermustnowprefertoaccepttheoffer,asshowninFig.4.Bythesametoken,changing maychangetheupperthresholdx.Bytheconvexityofpreferencesandthelinearitywithrespecttovariationsofofthe maximum-possiblereward(E−x),itisimmediatelyobviousthatanincreaseincannotbeassociatedwithanincreasein theupperacceptancethreshold(andmoreoftenthannot,itwillleadtoadecreaseinx).

Intheprecedingparagraphs,wehavepresentedqualitativepredictionsthatcanbederivedfromthegeneralmodelby Coxetal.(2008).Virtuallyallofthesepredictionshavebeenweak,inthesenseexemplifiedbythestatementthat“foroffers ofdecreasinggenerosity,theresponsecannotincrease.”Byemployingweakinequalitiesinalloftheirdefinitions,Coxetal.

(2008)encompassalloftheexistingmodelpredictionsinoneframework.Themodelwouldbeabletoaccountevenfor offer-responsefunctionsequaltoastrictlypositiveconstant,incontrasttoanyoftheothermodels.Itdoesplaceanumber ofrestrictionsonbehaviorthatcanbeexpected,mostnotablyperhapstherequirementofacertaindegreeofconsistency.

However,itdoesnotmakeclearpredictionsliketheremainingmodelspresented.Inotherwords,whatthemodelgainsin generality,itloosesintermsofspecifity.Weconsiderthisanimportantshortcomingandbrieflyreviewpotentialdirections ofmodelrefinementtoeschewthisprobleminSection5ofthisarticle.Topreparethefloorfortheresults,wesummarize thepredictionsfromthedifferentmodelsinTable1.

4. Results

Westructurethepresentationofourresultsasfollows:first,wecharacterizerejectionbehaviorofresponders.Second,we analyzeresponsepatterns.Third,wesystematicallyrelateresponsepatternstorejectionbehavior.Werelegatepresentation ofdataonoffers,expectedoffers,aswellasofrole-contingentaveragepayoffstotheonlinesupplementarymaterial(available onthejournal’swebsite),asthesearenotinthefocusofthisstudy.

4.1. Rejections

84%ofactualoffersin thehigh- condition(81%inthelow-condition) wereaccepted.Followingourtheoretical discussionfromtheprevioussection,wedefineanupperandaloweracceptancethresholdforeachresponderi,xiandxi, asfollows:

12Onceagain,thisrequiresinvokingtheincreasingbenevolenceproperty,cf.footnote11.

13Strictlyspeaking,thisstatementisnotcorrect.Please,refertothediscussioninSection5forwhyweholdtheaboveassertiontobeinthespiritofthe model.

(9)

Table1

Predictionsofthemodelsdiscussed.

Responsey(x)tooffers 0<x<x x>x

Payoff-maximization Notapplicable:alloffersareaccepted

Inequityaversion x x

Reciprocity(linear/non-linear/mixed) 0 Ex

Coxetal.(2008)y/x0 y>Ex,y/x0

Treatmenteffectony(x) 0<x<x x>x

Payoff-maximization Notapplicable:alloffersareaccepted

Inequityaversion + +

Reciprocity(linear/non-linear/mixed) 0

Coxetal.(2008) +or0

Acceptancethresholds x/ x/

Payoff-maximization Notapplicable:alloffersareaccepted

Inequityaversion +

Reciprocity(linear/non-linear/mixed) + (0/−or0/0)

Coxetal.(2008) +or0 or0

Note:Derivationsforpredictionsunderexcessivelyniceoffersareomitted.

Table2

Numbersofrespondersaccordingtoacceptancethresholds.

xi xi

−1 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 9 10 11 12

high- 0 3 5 5 9 42 11 1 1 1 10 64

low- 1 8 6 9 19 27 6 1 0 1 5 71

xi = max{x|ıi(x)=1}and

xi =

max{x|x≤6,ıi(x)=0}, if{x|x≤6,ıi(x)=0}=/∅,and

−1, otherwise,

(5)

whereıi(x)denotestheacceptancedecisionofresponderiforacertainofferx.Notethatinequityaversionandreciprocity modelspredictregularitywithrespecttorejections,thatis,ıi(x)=1,∀x∈(xi,xi],andıi(x)=0,otherwise.Intotal,32outof 153respondersexhibitrejectiondecisionsthatviolateregularity.Whilethisismorethantypicallyobserved(seeCamerer, 2003),only9ofthem(6%ofallresponders)makemorethanonedecisionthatwouldcontradictregularity.Weattribute theremaining23violationstothedifficultyarisingfromtherandom-orderone-by-onepresentationofpossibleoffers.To accountforthisfactanduseasmuchinformationaspossible,wechosetheabovedefinitionofxi.14Thefurtheranalysis includesthedataofallresponders.Respondersareclassifiedaccordingtotheiracceptancethresholds;Table2reportsthe numberofrespondersineachlowerandupperacceptanceclass,||xi||and||xi||,respectively.

Thelowerthresholdsxiaresignificantlyhigherinhigh-(withanaverageof3.57vs.2.97inlow-,p=0.003;also,ascan beeasilyseenfromTable2,xifromthehigh-treatmentfirst-orderstatisticallydominatesxifromthelow-condition).15 Atthesametime,thetreatmentdifferencebetweenupperacceptancethresholdsxifailstoreachsignificance(11.80vs.

11.91,p=0.114).However,thisisnotastrongindicationthatthereisnoeffect:whilemostrespondersneverrejectanoffer abovetheequalsplit,thenumberofthosewhodoinhigh-(12outof76)isdoublethecorrespondingnumberfromthe low-treatment(6outof77;again,statisticaldominanceholds).

4.2. Responses

Givenourmainresearchinterestliesinthestudyofreciprocalbehavior,responsesfollowingarejectionarethecentral elementinouranalysis.Inthefollowing,wewillidentifyrejectedoffersasxr,sothattheresponsetoarejectedofferisy(xr).

Inlightoftheexploratorynatureofourstudy,wewanttogetascloseaspossibletotherawdata.Therefore,weclassifythe responsefunctionsaccordingtomutuallyexclusivetypecategories.Wedefinethetypesbasedonthetheoreticalpredictions summarizedinTable1,focussingonthenegative-reciprocitypart,giventhereislittlevarianceinthedomainofpositive

14Ourqualitativeresultsandstatisticalinferencesdonotchangeifwedefinexiusingthemorestraightforwarddefinitionxi=min{x|ıi(x)=1},indicating therobustnessofourfindings.

15Unlessotherwiseindicated,allcomparisonsarebasedontwo-sidedWilcoxonrank-sumtests.Behaviorofeconomists/mathematiciansandother participantsdoesnotdiffersignificantlywithrespecttoanyvariablemeasured.

(10)

Table3

Frequencyofrespondertypes.

High- (in%) Low- (in%)

Null 3 3.9 6 7.8

Accepters 0 0.0 1 1.3

Symbolic 2 2.6 1 1.3

Gentlepunishers 3 3.9 3 3.9

Inequity-averse 14 18.4 12 15.6

Reciprocal:linear 13 17.1 29 37.7

Reciprocal:gradual 33 43.4 20 26.0

Between 3 3.9 3 3.9

Unclassified 5 6.6 2 2.6

Total 76 77

reciprocity.Participantswhoseresponsescouldnotbefittedintothecategoriesdefinedbythepresentedmodelswere groupedaccordingtothebroadcharacteristicsoftheirresponses.

Null.Subjectsfallingintothiscategoryacceptalloffersexceptforoffersx=0,inwhichcasetheyrespondbyy(0)=0.This behaviorcanbeclassifiedaseitherselfish,inequity-averseorreciprocal,andthereforedoesnotprovidemuchinformation aboutthenulls’motivations.

Accepters.Subjectsfallingintothiscategoryacceptalloffers.

Symbolic.Subjectsfallingintothiscategoryacceptmostoffersbutrejectatleastone.However,theirrejectionisonly symbolic–theyadministertheproposertheamountthelatteraskedfor:y(xr)=E−xr.

Gentlepunishers.Subjectsfallingintothiscategoryrejectsomeoffersbutleavetheproposerbetteroffthanwhatthey wereofferedforxr<6,i.e.,y(xr)>xr.

Inequity-averse.Inequity-averseplayersconformtothepredictionsofthecorrespondingmodels:whenevertheyreject anofferxrwhichtheydoforatleasttwooffersx,theyrespondbychoosingy(xr)=xr.

Reciprocal:linear.Subjectsfallingintothiscategoryconformtothepredictionsofallmajorreciprocitymodels:whenever theyrejectanofferxrwhichtheydoforatleasttwooffersx,theyrespondbypunishingtheotherplayerasharshlyas possible,y(xr)=0.

Reciprocal:gradual.Subjectsfallingintothiscategoryexhibittwocharacteristics:(i)theyarenotinequity-averseplayers and(ii)theirofferresponsefunctionfulfillsy(xj)≥y(xi)foranypairofrejectedoffersxiandxjsuchthatxi<xjandy(xj)>y(xi) foratleastonesuchpair.

Between.Subjectsarecategorizedtofallinbetweentheothercategoriesiftheyrejectvariousoffersandchoosey(xr)such thattheywouldbelongtodifferentcategoriesfordifferentxr.

Table3summarizestheresultsofourclassificationanalysis.16Wemakethefollowingobservations:First,takinginto accountallresponsepatternsthatcouldpotentiallyresultfrompreferencesofapayoff-maximizingplayer–null,accepters, onesymbolictypeineachtreatmentplusonegentle-punisher–wecountonly13participants(4inhigh-,9inlow-)out of153(8%).Hence,comparedtotypicalresultsfromothervariationsoftheultimatumgame(e.g.,seeAndreonietal.,2003), theurmgameyieldsmuchless‘selfish’behaviorbyresponders.17

Second,thesumofallplayerswhosebehaviorcanbedescribedbyoneofthetheoreticmodelsoutlinedinSection3 excludingthemodelbyCoxetal.(2008)makesupforonly31outof76inhigh-and50outof77inlow-.Inother words,conventionalmodelsaccountforonlyabout40%(65%)oftheobservedresponsepatternsinhigh-(low-).More specifically,weobserveastable16-18%inequity-averseplayers,whilethenumberbelongingtodifferentsubclassesof reciprocitydifferssubstantiallyacrosstreatmentconditions.Mostparticipantsnotexhibitingbehavioraspredictedbythe abovemodelscanbecategorizedasgraduallyreciprocal.ThemodelofCoxetal.(2008)canaccountfortheseobservations.

However,itaccommodatesratherthanpredictsthem.Below,weexploreanumberofwaysinwhichourunderstandingof graduallyreciprocalbehaviormaybecharacterizedonthebasisoftheirmodel.

Third,inhigh-,thefractionofplayerscategorizedasgradualreciprocatorsishigherthaninlow-byalmost20%.Atthe sametime,thehigh-fractionoflinear-reciprocalplayersislowerbythesame20%.Inotherwords,thedatalookasifachange infrom0.5to0.25changedtheresponsefunctionofabout20%ofthepopulationsuchthattheynolongerdifferentiatethe severityofpunishmentwithrespecttoanoffer’sunkindness.18Whetherthisisanactualtypeshiftorwhetheritismerely theslopeoftheresponsefunctionbeingshifteddownwardverystronglyissomethingwecannotanswer.Whatwedoknow isthatthefractionofgradualreciprocatorswitharesponse–functionslopelargerthan0.4changesfrom17outof33in

16Notethatweallowedforasingledeviationfromtherespectivepredictions;thiscouldbeanacceptancebelowxioraslightnon-monotonicity,e.g.,for gradualreciprocators.Notdoingsowouldleaveuswith24(12)gradualreciprocatorsinhigh-(low-),andwith20(13)unclassifiedresponders.

17Aplausiblereasonforthisobservationisthatpunishmentcostsarelowerinoursetup.Wearethankfultoananonymousrefereeforpointingthisout.

18A 2-testsuggeststhatthetypedistributionsofparticipantsclassifiableaspayoff-maximising,inequity-averse,linear-reciprocal,graduallyreciprocal, andothers,differbetweentreatments,(p=0.015).

(11)

Table4

Meanloweracceptancethresholdsbytreatmentandtype.

Respondertype HIGH LOW

Inequity-averse 4.08 3.50

Reciprocal:linear 3.71 3.31

Reciprocal:gradual 4.00 3.15

high-to5outof20inlow-.Inotherwords,responsesingeneraldogetharsherwithincreasingfixedcostsofpunishment alsowithinthegroupofgradualreciprocators.

Inourview,theseobservationsarecritical:furtherdevelopmentofanyreciprocitymodelshouldaccountforbothgrad- uallyreciprocalbehaviorandwhatlookslikeaparameter-inducedshiftinthetypedistribution,ifitistobeseenasastep forwardinourunderstandingofreciprocalbehavior.Forthisreason,wedevoteSection5tosomeideasonpossibledirections inwhichtoextendexistingmodelsofreciprocity,discussingtheminlightofourobservations.Beforewedoso,weshed somelightontheinteractionbetweenresponsepatternsandrejectionsinthefollowingpart.

4.3. Theinteractionbetweenresponsepatternsandrejections

Inthefollowingparagraph,webrieflyreporttheresultsofacomparisonofloweracceptancethresholdsbetweenthethree maintypes,reportedinTable4.Whilewedonotfindanysignificantdifferencesofloweracceptancethresholdsbetween inequity-averse,linear-reciprocal,andgraduallyreciprocalplayerswithineachtreatment(allpair-wisecomparisonsyield p>0.15),weobserveaverydifferentiatedpictureacrosstreatments.Bothforinequity-averseandlinear-reciprocalplayers, thetreatmentdifferencein loweracceptancethresholdsisinthepredicteddirectionbutclearlyfailstobesignificant (p=0.249andp=0.301,respectively).However,forparticipantsclassifiedasgradualreciprocators,thereisatreatment effect:inlow-,theyacceptsignificantlyloweroffersthaninhigh-(p<0.001).Thusforasubstantialfractionofthese players,fairnessconsiderationsaresubstantiallyinfluencedbyasituationalvariation.Onepossiblereadingofthisisthat playerswithhighacceptancethresholdsexhibitparticularsensitivitytothefixedcostsofpunishment:iftheirresponse functionshiftsenoughsothatinlow-,theyareclassifiedaslinearreciprocators,thiswouldexplainthe(non-)significance ofthetreatmentcomparisonsofbothlinearandgradualreciprocators.Onceagain,furtherresearchisneededtoassessthe plausibilityofthisinterpretation.

5. Generalized-reciprocalbehavior

Inthissection,wesetouttoexplorepossibledirectionsinwhichexistingmodelsmaybechangedtoaccountforour findings.Ourdatacallfortwothings.Thepresenceofasubstantialfractionofparticipantswhocanbecategorizedasgradual reciprocatorscallsforatheoreticcharacterizationofsuchplayers.Andtheshiftinthetypedistributioninresponsetoour treatmentvariationcallsforatheorythatisabletopredictthatshift.Ourdiscussionofwaystomeetthesechallengeswill bedividedintotwoparts.First,wereviewanddiscardasimpleextensionoflinearmodelsofreciprocity.Subsequently,we provideamoredetaileddiscussionwithinthemodelofCoxetal.(2008),payingtributetothefactthatitistheonlyavailable modelabletoaccommodateourfindings.

5.1. Linearreciprocitymodels

Inthereciprocitymodelsreviewedinthispaper,therearetwocomponentsofreciprocalbehavior:anassessmentof theotherplayer’skindness,orgenerosity,andthedegreeofreciprocation,oraltruisminaplayer’sresponse.Linearmodels likeCharnessandRabin(2002),DufwenbergandKirchsteiger(2004),orFalkandFischbacher(2006)aggregateanaction’s degreeofgenerosityintoa(relative)weightthatisputontheotherplayer’spayoff;thedegreeofkindnessof–oraltruismin –aresponsethenfollowsfromthemaximizationoftheweightedpayoffsum.Averysimpleideathatwouldbeabletomeet bothchallengesposedbyourdataistomodifythemodelsbyspecifyingplayers’utilityfunctionsuchthatitismaximizedif thedegreeofaltruismmeetsacertaintarget,namelythedegreeofgenerosityoftheotherplayer’saction.Thisisakintowhat mostlegalsystemsdo:matchingpunishmenttotheseverityofanoffence,ratherthanassigningthemaximumpenaltyto allinfringementsalike.

Inprinciple,therearethreewaystoapplythisideatoourgame;however,onlyoneofthemcanaddressbothchallenges posedbyourdata.Asintheearlierreciprocitymodels,aresponderwouldevaluatekindnessagainstthe‘fairness’orneutrality benchmark(inourgame,presumablycorrespondingtotheequalsplit),sothatthedegreeofgenerositytobematchedis givenbyx/6.Afterarejection,theresponderwouldassigntheproposertheabovefraction(i)oftheproposer’sfairshareof6, yieldingy(x)=6·x/6=x,(ii)oftheproposer’sclaim,sothaty(x)=(12−x)·x/6,or(iii)oftheproposer’sclaimaftershrinking

Referenzen

ÄHNLICHE DOKUMENTE

Electro-assisted removal of polar and ionic organic compounds from water using activated carbon

Particularly since the early 1970s, states have established a complex system of international treaties that regulate their rights and duties in different maritime spaces

Bioenergy, Germany, renewable energy systems, bioenergy carbon capture and storage, 46.. integrated assessment, climate policy

Effects of electrokinetic phenomena on bacterial deposition monitored by quartz crystal microbalance with dissipation

The world needs effective thermal insulation of buildings for pollution control and energy savings. Optimum thermal, fire and acoustic insulations are achieved by using

In particular, we focus on the thermodynamic aspects of the adsorption process, including dimensional inconsistency of fitted parameters, Temkin isotherm assumptions,

Correlations of dissolved organic carbon (DOC), total nitrogen (TN), ammonia (NH4), and total phosphorus (TN) concentration with selected variables (C3/Tryp and specific

Prediction of soil organic carbon and the C:N ratio on a national scale using machine learning and satellite data: A comparison between Sentinel-2, Sentinel-3 and Landsat-8